Statistical ensemble interpretation done right

  • #71
lodbrok said:
Is the system "an electron" or "an ensemble of similarly prepared electrons"?
That depends on which QM interpretation you are using. In statistical ensemble interpretations such as the OP describes, yes, the quantum state refers to an ensemble of electrons (more precisely, the spin-1/2 degree of freedom of the outermost electron in neutral silver atoms) all coming from the same preparation process.

lodbrok said:
Whether you use a single CERN or one million CERNS, do the results of the measurements tell you about "an electron" or "an ensemble of similarly prepared electrons." (or preparation procedure).
Same answer as above.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
PeterDonis said:
That depends on which QM interpretation you are using. In statistical ensemble interpretations such as the OP describes, yes, the quantum state refers to an ensemble of electrons (more precisely, the spin-1/2 degree of freedom of the outermost electron in neutral silver atoms) all coming from the same preparation process.Same answer as above.
Thank you, but the question was for vanhees in response to his statement that "the system" was "an electron", which implies a different interpretation than what I remember him using previously.
 
  • #73
lodbrok said:
the question was for vanhees
In post #67 he seems to be using an interpretation in which the quantum state describes the preparation procedure directly, as opposed to describing either an individual system produced by that procedure or an ensemble of such systems. But I agree it would be good for him to clarify.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #74
vanhees71 said:
Once more, this is a misconception of the quantum state. The quantum state of the system you want to observe has nothing to do with the measurement device but with the preparation of this system.
There are indeed interpretations where the quantum state of the system has nothing to do with what I intent to measure on the system. But if a minimal statistical interpretation wants to keep some "operational verification" meaning, then it has to be a bit more careful at that point:
gentzen said:
If you look at SEI from an operational verification perspective, then yes, you must associate a single system with a state before you know the results of the non-preparation measurements. This allows it to take part in some verification. Of course, no statistical verification can ever fully reject your state assignments, at most it can tell you that winning the jackpot of a lottery would have been more probable than your obtained measurement results given your previous state assignments.
The issue arises, because the statistical verification requires a limit process of accumulating measurement statistics. But this limit process requires that the equivalence classes of preparation procedures are kept fixed during the verification. And what I intent to measure on the system can impact those equivalence classes.

Now I admit that "good taste" allows to relax those "rules" significantly in practice. But the idealized description should still be the one explained above. It is simply too easy to fool oneself with statistics, not least because our human intuition is not very good in that domain.

vanhees71 said:
For me Heisenberg and Bohr wrote the most incomprehensible papers compared to the other "founding fathers" of QT. ... Heisenberg had ingenious ideas but always needed translators to clarify his insights for the normal physicist. This usually were Born and Jordan but also very much Pauli.

The most underrated of all these was Born, who was really the one recognizing the mathematics behind Heisenberg's weird Helgoland paper, which reflects the discovery process of the Göttingen group pretty nicely. Also see
https://arxiv.org/abs/2306.00842
Indeed, looks like Heisenberg needed both Born and Pauli. Jordan, not so sure, the paper is consistent with what I learned from other sources. He didn't do himself a favor by being cavalier with truth. Maybe Paul Ehrenfest is even more underrated than Born:
Einstein’s enduring estimate appears in his response to a letter from Paul Ehrenfest. To Ehrenfest’s remark that, despite his relative nothingness, Einstein and Bohr had always supported his work, "whereas contact with other theorists totally discourages me," Einstein replied that like himself and Bohr, Ehrenfest was a Principienfuchser, a worrier about foundations, while most other theorists were virtuosi, polished mathematicians or devotees of detail, but not quite the real thing. He gave as examples of the polished virtuoso Born and his predecessor at Göttingen, Debye.
The award of the Nobel prize to Born in 1954 made a perfect emblem of the “great adventure." It brought out the main distinguishing feature of the new physics, its radically probabilistic basis, and implied its coherence and completeness by rewarding the co-inventor of MM for his elucidation of its rival WM. The earlier reservations about Born's contributions were ignored or forgotten. And so the Nobel establishment gave a fifth prize for wave mechanics, including those awarded in 1937 for the "experimental discovery of the diffraction of electrons." MM could boast but one.

vanhees71 said:
What I dislike is his nebulous writing and overemphasizing philosophy over physics.
Well, thanks for answering me. I understand that you dislike his overemphasizing philosophy over physics. The general accusation of nebulous writing without reference to concrete papers or books suggests to me that you actually have not read much of his writings. Perhaps you tried to read his breakthrough paper, and didn't get what you hoped for.

vanhees71 said:
He also had many misconceptions, which for some reason unfortunately still stuck in modern textbooks (although they don't play much of a role anymore in contemporary research), e.g., his first paper about the meaning of the uncertainty relation, which he first published claiming it were about the disturbance of the system by interaction with the measurement device, which leads to the misconception discussed in the first part of this posting.
Trying to turn one concrete misconception into a general accusation of many misconceptions again suggests to me that you are simply not very familiar with much of Heisenberg's work. Maybe you would also cite his infamous unified field theory of elementary particles as another example of his misconceptions. But both concrete misconceptions are common knowledge concerning Heisenberg, not an indication of any non-trivial familiarity with this work.

Anyway, thanks again for your answer. I always have to force myself to write an answer in cases where I am not so sure about my answer, because I know that it would be impolite if I just stayed silent. But still, sometimes staying silent is actually a good idea.
 
  • #75
gentzen said:
the statistical verification requires a limit process of accumulating measurement statistics. But this limit process requires that the equivalence classes of preparation procedures are kept fixed during the verification.
Yes.

gentzen said:
And what I intent to measure on the system can impact those equivalence classes.
No, it doesn't. You can do different measurements on systems that were prepared by the same preparation procedure. The preparation procedure (or equivalence class of such procedures--but in the case under discussion, the SG experiment, there was only one preparation procedure so the "equivalence class" question is moot) is modeled by the quantum state. The measurement you make is modeled by an operator. The two are distinct and independent.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #76
gentzen said:
Jordan, not so sure, the paper is consistent with what I learned from other sources. He didn't do himself a favor by being cavalier with truth.
Here I found a favorable account of Jordan's contributions:
It was Jordan, more than anyone else, who developed a mathematically elegant formulation of matrix mechanics (Born and Jordan 1925; 1926). It was Jordan who went on to consolidate matrix mechanics with Dirac’s alternative operator calculus (Dirac 1925) and Erwin Schrödinger’s wave-mechanical formulation (Schrödinger 1926a; 1926b) in the comprehensive formalism known as statistical transformation theory (Jordan 1927a; 1927b, see also Duncan and Janssen 2009). It was Jordan who did more than anyone other than Dirac to inaugurate the program of quantum field theory, in ways such as developing the second quantization approach and being the first to discover the problem of divergences in quantum field theory (Jordan and Klein 1927; Jordan and Wigner 1928). And it was Jordan who, along with von Neumann and Eugene Wigner, was developing more abstract algebraic frameworks for quantum mechanics (Jordan 1933b; Jordan et.al. 1934).
But in case you believe that Jordan was less deep into philosophy than Heisenberg, see:
https://www.informationphilosopher.com/solutions/scientists/jordan/
 
  • #77
gentzen said:
And what I intent to measure on the system can impact those equivalence classes.
PeterDonis said:
No, it doesn't. You can do different measurements on systems that were prepared by the same preparation procedure. The preparation procedure (or equivalence class of such procedures--but in the case under discussion, the SG experiment, there was only one preparation procedure so the "equivalence class" question is moot) is modeled by the quantum state. The measurement you make is modeled by an operator. The two are distinct and independent.
To stay with the SG experiment, should a different isotope composition of the beam of silver atoms be considered to be a different preparation procedure? It doesn't matter for the correlation between spin and momentum. It has a slight impact on the correlation between momentum and position. And if it were important to us, we could simply measure the isotope composition of "our" beam. For some experiments, it might even be important for the beam to consists only of a single isotope, because of its impact on the exact trajectory.
 
  • #78
PeterDonis said:
In post #67 he seems to be using an interpretation in which the quantum state describes the preparation procedure directly, as opposed to describing either an individual system produced by that procedure or an ensemble of such systems. But I agree it would be good for him to clarify.
The quantum state is the formal description of a preparation procedure on a single system. In this sense the quantum state refers to the single system. The meaning of the quantum state is, of course, entirely statistical, i.e., the possible outcome of any observable is given by Born's rule, i.e., the possible outcomes are the eigenvalues of the self-adjoint operator, representing the measured observable, ##\hat{O}##. Then let ##|o,\alpha \rangle## be the complete orthonormal set of eigenvectors of ##\hat{O}## with the eigenvalue ##o##, then given the quantum state ##\hat{\rho}##, the probablity to get ##o## when measuring ##O## (the observable is defined by a measurement procedure) then is given by
$$P(o|\hat{\rho})=\sum_{\alpha} \langle o,\alpha|\hat{\rho}|o,\alpha \rangle.$$
This can, of course, only be verified experimentally by preparing an ensemble of independently prepared systems in the state described by ##\hat{\rho}##.
 
  • #79
gentzen said:
There are indeed interpretations where the quantum state of the system has nothing to do with what I intent to measure on the system. But if a minimal statistical interpretation wants to keep some "operational verification" meaning, then it has to be a bit more careful at that point:
That's the standard interpretation and practice in real-world physics laboratories. There's some preparation procedure (e.g., set up a Ag-atom beam by heating up silver in an oven with a little hole, letting it go through some slits to collimate it, etc.) and independently you can measure any observable on the so prepared system you like (e.g., the component of its spin in an arbitrary direction by putting a corresponding magnetic field in this direction and a screen registering the Ag atoms at the corresponding places behind the magnet; the magnet entangles the spin component with the position at the screen modulo some small systematical error since the inhomogenous magnetic field has at least a small component in a different direction).
gentzen said:
The issue arises, because the statistical verification requires a limit process of accumulating measurement statistics. But this limit process requires that the equivalence classes of preparation procedures are kept fixed during the verification. And what I intent to measure on the system can impact those equivalence classes.
Of course, the preparation procedure has to be kept fixed to get an ensemble described by the intended state you want to investigate.
gentzen said:
Now I admit that "good taste" allows to relax those "rules" significantly in practice. But the idealized description should still be the one explained above. It is simply too easy to fool oneself with statistics, not least because our human intuition is not very good in that domain.
I've no clue, what you mean by this. This has nothing to do with QT but holds for any statistics, including "classical statistics".
gentzen said:
Indeed, looks like Heisenberg needed both Born and Pauli. Jordan, not so sure, the paper is consistent with what I learned from other sources. He didn't do himself a favor by being cavalier with truth. Maybe Paul Ehrenfest is even more underrated than Born:
Jordan was behind most of the math. E.g., he helped born to prove the famous commutation relation between position and momentum, he developed em-field quantization (in 1925/26 before Dirac!), etc. He is the most underrated of the founding fathers of QT. That's partially, because he was "too mathematical" for the taste of many physicists but also because he was foolish enough with his political involvement with the Nazis in 1933-1945.
gentzen said:
Well, thanks for answering me. I understand that you dislike his overemphasizing philosophy over physics. The general accusation of nebulous writing without reference to concrete papers or books suggests to me that you actually have not read much of his writings. Perhaps you tried to read his breakthrough paper, and didn't get what you hoped for.
I read the Helgoland paper. Of course, you can understand it, having learnt the elaborated theory nearly 100 years later. If you, however, try to understand it without assuming this knowledge, it's hopeless. Matrix Mechanics was worked out in clear mathematical form by Born and Jordan (of course under participation of Heisenberg) shortly afterwards.
gentzen said:
Trying to turn one concrete misconception into a general accusation of many misconceptions again suggests to me that you are simply not very familiar with much of Heisenberg's work. Maybe you would also cite his infamous unified field theory of elementary particles as another example of his misconceptions. But both concrete misconceptions are common knowledge concerning Heisenberg, not an indication of any non-trivial familiarity with this work.
Sure, it's telling. Pauli withdraw his name from the paper before publication. I think I'm quite famliar with QT in a hopefully not too trivial way ;-).
gentzen said:
Anyway, thanks again for your answer. I always have to force myself to write an answer in cases where I am not so sure about my answer, because I know that it would be impolite if I just stayed silent. But still, sometimes staying silent is actually a good idea.
Well, one can only learn something in these matters by discussions.
 
  • #80
If I prepare single-electron states, I deal with a single electron. Of course, as with any experiment, I have to prepare and entire ensemble of a single-electron state to verify the probabilistic predictions implied by this preparation. I don't need a million of CERNs to prepare an ensemble of proton or heavy-ion beams. This I can do with 1 CERN as is done in the real world ;-)).
 
  • #81
vanhees71 said:
The quantum state is the formal description of a preparation procedure on a single system. In this sense the quantum state refers to the single system. The meaning of the quantum state is, of course, entirely statistical, i.e., the possible outcome of any observable is given by Born's rule, i.e., the possible outcomes are the eigenvalues of the self-adjoint operator, representing the measured observable, ##\hat{O}##. Then let ##|o,\alpha \rangle## be the complete orthonormal set of eigenvectors of ##\hat{O}## with the eigenvalue ##o##, then given the quantum state ##\hat{\rho}##, the probablity to get ##o## when measuring ##O## (the observable is defined by a measurement procedure) then is given by
$$P(o|\hat{\rho})=\sum_{\alpha} \langle o,\alpha|\hat{\rho}|o,\alpha \rangle.$$
This can, of course, only be verified experimentally by preparing an ensemble of independently prepared systems in the state described by ##\hat{\rho}##.
Just a side comment, that this is just one possible interpretation. I know that you are clarifying what you view is, but there are other possibilities. For example you have interpretations where the state describes the ensemble of equally prepared systems, not any single system.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #82
This is not an interpretation, that's how QT is used in analyzing real experiments.

To build an ensemble you have to prepare single systems independently from each other. So there must be a meaning of "state" for a single system, and that's the preparation procedure (or rather an "equivalence class of preparation procedures") applied repeatedly to many single systems to prepare an ensemble.

Since the physical meaning described by the state, ##\hat{\rho}##, is entirely probabilistic, you can say that it indeed describes an ensemble in the sense that the probabilities it predicts, can only be observed on (sufficiently large) ensembles, but to build the ensemble you have to refer to each single member of this ensemble, and that leads to the operational meaning of the state as a preparation procedure.
 
  • Like
  • Skeptical
Likes weirdoguy, Fra and gentzen
  • #83
vanhees71 said:
This is not an interpretation, that's how QT is used in analyzing real experiments.
No, it is an interpretation. I think you are confused about it, and you don't see the difference.
vanhees71 said:
To build an ensemble you have to prepare single systems independently from each other.
The ensemble in this interpretation is an abstract entity. You don't build it. You cannot build it. It is an equivalent class, it ha infinitely many members.
vanhees71 said:
So there must be a meaning of "state" for a single system, and that's the preparation procedure (or rather an "equivalence class of preparation procedures") applied repeatedly to many single systems to prepare an ensemble.
Why there must be? Just because you prefer it that way?
vanhees71 said:
Since the physical meaning described by the state, ##\hat{\rho}##, is entirely probabilistic, you can say that it indeed describes an ensemble in the sense that the probabilities it predicts, can only be observed on (sufficiently large) ensembles, but to build the ensemble you have to refer to each single member of this ensemble, and that leads to the operational meaning of the state as a preparation procedure.
And as I said, there infinitely many members in the ensemble, what do you mean by "build it"?
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #84
martinbn said:
The ensemble in this interpretation is an abstract entity.
I in part agree, but isnt the probabilistic embedding of a single instance as well?

But approximately information encoded in the macro environment (rhe lab and all its computers) is real, and not an astraction. Its how i would defend this.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #85
martinbn said:
And as I said, there infinitely many members in the ensemble, what do you mean by "build it"?
How about that the environment(observer) is "learning" about what state distribution the preparation produces. Building ~ learning, tuning the procedure? Makes sens to me.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #86
martinbn said:
No, it is an interpretation. I think you are confused about it, and you don't see the difference.

The ensemble in this interpretation is an abstract entity. You don't build it. You cannot build it. It is an equivalent class, it ha infinitely many members.
It's not an abstract entity, it's a real-world item to be investigated with real-world experimental setups.
martinbn said:
Why there must be? Just because you prefer it that way?
You must be able to associate the abstract entity ##\hat{\rho}## ("statistical operator") of the formalism with the real-world system you want to investigate, and that's the preparation procedure done on this system in the real-world experiment you do with it.
martinbn said:
And as I said, there infinitely many members in the ensemble, what do you mean by "build it"?
In a real-world experiment there's a finite ensemble, and you have the corresponding statistical errors (in addition to the usually also apparent systematical ones) when comparing the predicted probabilities to the measured averages over a finite ensemble.
 
  • Sad
Likes weirdoguy
  • #87
vanhees71 said:
It's not an abstract entity, it's a real-world item to be investigated with real-world experimental setups.

You must be able to associate the abstract entity ##\hat{\rho}## ("statistical operator") of the formalism with the real-world system you want to investigate, and that's the preparation procedure done on this system in the real-world experiment you do with it.

In a real-world experiment there's a finite ensemble, and you have the corresponding statistical errors (in addition to the usually also apparent systematical ones) when comparing the predicted probabilities to the measured averages over a finite ensemble.
You are simply making claims based on a different interpretation instead of providing any arguments!!! You cannot reject one interpretation using another!
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #88
martinbn said:
For example you have interpretations where the state describes the ensemble of equally prepared systems, not any single system.
How would one(an observer or a physicists) alternatically practically or operationally determine/define the probabilistic description of a single system by any level of confidence? unless history repeats itself. In a way one might say that provided that field quanta are indiguishable, can we really say wether history DID repeat itself, or if we observed the "same thing once again", without using auxiliary information? (would that be cheating btw?)

/Fredrik
 
  • #89
Fra said:
How would one(an observer or a physicists) alternatically practically or operationally determine/define the probabilistic description of a single system by any level of confidence?
What do yiu mean by that? Once the system is prepared, you can make only one measurment. After that the system is no longer in the same prepararion.
Fra said:
unless history repeats itself. In a way one might say that provided that field quanta are indiguishable, can we really say wether history DID repeat itself, or if we observed the "same thing once again", without using auxiliary information? (would that be cheating btw?)

/Fredrik
 
  • Haha
Likes gentzen
  • #90
gentzen said:
To stay with the SG experiment, should a different isotope composition of the beam of silver atoms be considered to be a different preparation procedure?
That would depend on how much detail about the state you want to represent. In the usual treatment of the SG experiment, all the details that the isotope composition can affect are left out.
 
  • #91
vanhees71 said:
It's not an abstract entity, it's a real-world item to be investigated with real-world experimental setups.
Not according to, for example, Ballentine, Section 2.1. From p. 46 in my edition:

"However, it is important to remember that [the] ensemble is the conceptual infinite set of all such systems that may potentially result from the state preparation procedure, and not a concrete set of systems that coexist in space."

vanhees71 said:
In a real-world experiment there's a finite ensemble
Ballentine disagrees with this as well. In addition to the above, there is this from the same page:

"In the example of the scattering experiment, the system is a single particle, and the ensemble is the conceptual set of replicas of one particle in its surroundings. The ensemble should not be confused with a beam of particles, which is another kind of (many-particle) system."
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy and martinbn
  • #92
martinbn said:
What do yiu mean by that? Once the system is prepared, you can make only one measurment.
That's of course the problem, but I meant that to me my question to you :oldbiggrin:

I understand the matheamtical concept that you have imaginary ensembles, but the the question is, how do you justify this probabilistic reasoning, in an empirical and setting (that at least in principle, is doable for the class of "obsevers" we entertain, in a real interaction), without beeing able to repeating the process.

/Fredrik
 
  • #93
Fra said:
how do you justify this probabilistic reasoning, in an empirical and setting (that at least in principle, is doable for the class of "obsevers" we entertain, in a real interaction), without beeing able to repeating the process
You can repeat the process. That is the whole point of having a preparation procedure that you can run the same way many times.
 
  • #94
PeterDonis said:
You can repeat the process. That is the whole point of having a preparation procedure that you can run the same way many times.
Yes agreed. But I have a feeling we have some misunderstanding here.

I read martinb to suggest that, when do to repeat, it's no longer the SAME system. Ie. it's not the SAME electron beeing fired etc. And at the same time, he wants to attribute say the the density matrix to the system, and not the "ensemble" produced by a given preparation procedure given infinite number of samples?

I did I miss something?

/Fredrik
 
  • #95
Fra said:
I read martinb to suggest that, when do to repeat, it's no longer the SAME system.
It's not the same system, but that doesn't mean it's not the same preparation process. The same preparation process can prepare multiple systems.

Fra said:
at the same time, he wants to attribute say the the density matrix to the system, and not the "ensemble" produced by a given preparation procedure given infinite number of samples?
There are interpretations that do this. However, I'm not sure @martinbn is using one. Is there something specific he said that makes you think so?
 
  • #96
PeterDonis said:
It's not the same system, but that doesn't mean it's not the same preparation process. The same preparation process can prepare multiple systems.
Agreed.
PeterDonis said:
There are interpretations that do this. However, I'm not sure @martinbn is using one. Is there something specific he said that makes you think so?
I might have misinterpreted his post #81 as I read it it again.

What I meant in post #84 is that I agree that strictly speaking the ensemble as well as the p-distribution itself are fictions or abstractions. My point was based on that i thought it was questioned, without this empirical side, how do we justify the abstractions?

Does real observations or information processing approximate our theories, or is it the other way around? We interpret theories, but do we interpret information processing?

/Fredrik
 
  • #97
Fra said:
without this empirical side, how do we justify the abstractions?
We can't. We justify the abstractions ultimately by the fact that they make accurate predictions (if they do) about what we observe and measure empirically.

Fra said:
Does real observations or information processing approximate our theories, or is it the other way around? We interpret theories, but do we interpret information processing?
I'm not sure what role "information processing" plays here. We use our theories to construct models, and we compare the models with reality through their predictions about what we should observe and measure, compared with what we actually observe and measure. I'm not sure how this fits in to whatever picture you have. But that is how I would describe what is going on in as plain and simple language as I can.
 
  • #98
PeterDonis said:
We can't. We justify the abstractions ultimately by the fact that they make accurate predictions (if they do) about what we observe and measure empirically.
I don't think we disagree here, perhaps what martinb tried to say was unclear to me.
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure what role "information processing" plays here. We use our theories to construct models, and we compare the models with reality through their predictions about what we should observe and measure, compared with what we actually observe and measure.
Yes, thats the de facto information processing we do and what i meant in this case. Trying to stick to basics. In the more general picture but "information process" I would probably count every physical process in the macropscopic environment, that implicitl encodes information about subsystems. But the principle is the same.

Anyway, I can't see I disagree with you anywhere here.

/Fredrik
 
  • #99
Fra said:
Yes agreed. But I have a feeling we have some misunderstanding here.

I read martinb to suggest that, when do to repeat, it's no longer the SAME system. Ie. it's not the SAME electron beeing fired etc. And at the same time, he wants to attribute say the the density matrix to the system, and not the "ensemble" produced by a given preparation procedure given infinite number of samples?

I did I miss something?

/Fredrik
That is not what I meant. It is the same system, say the same electron, but it is not a member of the same ensemble any more. For example if it was prepared so that it is a member of the ensemble with state spin |up>, and you measure spin in a horizontal direction and you get "left", now this same electron is a member of an ensemble in the sate |left>. So any following measurement will be on the original system, but not as originally prepared.

And if you prepare another electron in the spin up, then it is not the same system, but it is still the same ensemble.
 
  • #100
Fra said:
perhaps what martinb tried to say was unclear to me
In post #81 he was just responding to the statement he quoted by @vanhees71. There is a difference between saying that the quantum state describes the results of a preparation procedure on a single system (which is what @vanhees71 said) and saying that the quantum state describes an ensemble of systems all prepared by the same preparation procedure (which is the type of interpretation that the title and OP of this thread refer to).
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and martinbn
  • #101
I don't understand, how you can build an ensemble to be in a given state, if you are not able to relate it to the preparation procedure on a single system. Otherwise I think @martinbn and I agree on the interpretation of the state, which as any probabilistic description refers to the properties of an ensemble, because you can experimentally test the probabilistic predictions only on an ensemble of equally prepared systems.

On the one hand the state thus is the description of a preparation procedure on a single system, but on the other the physical meaning of the state refers only to ensembles.
 
  • #102
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand, how you can build an ensemble to be in a given state, if you are not able to relate it to the preparation procedure on a single system. Otherwise I think @martinbn and I agree on the interpretation of the state, which as any probabilistic description refers to the properties of an ensemble, because you can experimentally test the probabilistic predictions only on an ensemble of equally prepared systems.

On the one hand the state thus is the description of a preparation procedure on a single system, but on the other the physical meaning of the state refers only to ensembles.
You misunderstood me. I am not saying how things are, but how things are according to one interpretation (which is not even my proffered one). You on the other hand are saying how things are according to a different interpretation. But in addition you claim that this is the only possibility and you think that your statements are interpretation independent. That is where we disagree.
 
  • #103
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand, how you can build an ensemble to be in a given state, if you are not able to relate it to the preparation procedure on a single system. Otherwise I think @martinbn and I agree on the interpretation of the state, which as any probabilistic description refers to the properties of an ensemble, because you can experimentally test the probabilistic predictions only on an ensemble of equally prepared systems.

On the one hand the state thus is the description of a preparation procedure on a single system, but on the other the physical meaning of the state refers only to ensembles.
A minimal statistical ensemble (MSE) proponent can certainly associate a state with a preparation procedure, but what motivates the MSE interpretation of a state as an infinite ensemble is the avoidance of pitfalls in thought processes. E.g. Both MSE and Copenhagen proponents can associate a state with a preparation procedure, but a Copenhagen proponent would happily proceed to think about measurement propensities in a single experimental run while an MSE proponent would not. They would only concern themselves with relative frequencies in several experimental runs and how they compare with rates in the infinite ensemble, as they are obliged to interpret the state as representing an infinite ensemble. They would hope to avoid ambiguities a Copenhagen proponent might be more vulnerable to.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, mattt, martinbn and 2 others
  • #104
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand, how you can build an ensemble to be in a given state, if you are not able to relate it to the preparation procedure on a single system.
The ensemble is not something that gets "built". It's an abstraction. Please read the passages from Ballentine that I referenced.
 
  • #105
It's not an abstraction. At colliders you prepare particles at pretty well determined momenta and let them collide (in fact it's bunches of many particles, but that are details not too relevant for the general argument). This you repeat zillion of times to "collect enough statistics". Particularly for "rare probes" (as my beloved "dileptons and photons" in heavy-ion collisions) you need a lot of statitics. One point of the recent upgrade of the LHC was to get higher luminosities to get "the statistics" in a shorter time. Another great challenge was to also adapt the detectors to cope with these higher rates!
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
84
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
789
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
47
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
91
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
22
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
19
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
16
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
6
Views
1K
Back
Top