Infinity: The Limit Concept and Cantor Transfinites

In summary: Supposedly, infininity has been purged from mathematics. Both the infinitely small and the infinitely large have been replaced by the idea of a "limit." In other words, the concept of infinity has been replaced by the concept of a limit in mathematics. This means that when dealing with infinite quantities, we do not consider them as literal infinities, but rather as the limiting value of an arbitrarily large number of terms.However, the idea of infinity introduced by Georg Cantor does allow for completed infinities. In his theory of sets, infinity is considered to be an actual quantity and there are even different levels or hierarchies of infinity.These seemingly opposed viewpoints are reconciled by recognizing that in mathematics, we use the concept
  • #1
Frank Peters
28
2
Supposedly, infininity has been purged from mathematics. Both the infinitely small and the infinitely large have been replaced by the idea of a "limit."

For example, a series x0+x1+x3+... is not considered to be a literal infinite sum with infinite terms but only the limiting value of an arbitrarily large number of terms.

In other words, an completed infinity makes no sense in the concept of limit.

However, the notion of infinity introduced by Georg Cantot does admit completed infinities. In Cantor's ideas, infinity does indeed exist an an actual quantity, and there are even a hierarchy of infinities.

How are these two seemingly opposed viewpoints reconciled? If we cannot define an actual sum of infinite terms because infinity has been replaced by the limit concept, how can we admit the actual infinities defined by Cantor?

I hope I am being clear. If not then let me know.
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Frank Peters said:
Supposedly, infininity has been purged from mathematics. Both the infinitely small and the infinitely large have been replaced by the idea of a "limit."

For example, a series x0+x1+x3+... is not considered to be a literal infinite sum with infinite terms but only the limiting value of an arbitrarily large number of terms.

In other words, an completed infinity makes no sense in the concept of limit.

However, the notion of infinity introduced by Georg Cantot does admit completed infinities. In Cantor's ideas, infinity does indeed exist an an actual quantity, and there are even a hierarchy of infinities.

How are these two seemingly opposed viewpoints reconciled? If we cannot define an actual sum of infinite terms because infinity has been replaced by the limit concept, how can we admit the actual infinities defined by Cantor?

I hope I am being clear. If not then let me know.

Cantor's theory has actual infinite objects, but there are no infinite (or infinitesimal) reals in the standard way of doing real numbers. So it's still true that proofs involving series involve limits, not actual infinity.
 
  • #3
Frank Peters said:
Supposedly, infininity has been purged from mathematics. Both the infinitely small and the infinitely large have been replaced by the idea of a "limit."
Maybe "infininity" :oldbiggrin: has been purged, but "infinity" still has a prominent role. As for limits, virtually every calculus textbook has statements such as the following:
##\lim_{x \to 0} \frac 1 {x^2} = \infty## and ##\lim_{x \to 0^-} \frac 1 x = -\infty##
Here the infinity symbols mean that the first fraction grows large without bound as x approaches 0, and that the second fraction becomes unboundedly negative as x approaches 0 from the negative side. Both of these limits can be stated more precisely and rigorously using variants of ##\delta-\epsilon## statements.
Frank Peters said:
For example, a series x0+x1+x3+... is not considered to be a literal infinite sum with infinite terms but only the limiting value of an arbitrarily large number of terms.
Not sure why your series is missing x2, but maybe that's just an oversight.

An expression such as ##x_0 + x_1 + x_2 + \dots ##, or ##\sum_{n = 0}^\infty x_n## is an example of an infinite series, and is understood to have an infinite number of terms. It's possible that for some values of the ##x_i## terms, the series will add up to (or converge to) some finite number, but for other values, the series will become unbounded or otherwise not converge to a specific value.

What you describe as "the limiting value of an arbitrarily large number of terms" might not exist at all. This infinite series, ##\sum_{n = 0}^\infty \frac 1 {2^n}## represents an infinite number of terms that add up to 1. This infinite series, ##\sum_{n = 1}^\infty \frac 1 n## is the so-called harmonic series. It can be proven that the sequence of partial sums is unbounded, meaning that this series diverges.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
Frank Peters said:
Supposedly, infinity has been purged from mathematics.
Who says that?
Both the infinitely small and the infinitely large have been replaced by the idea of a "limit."
I disagree. The concepts of infinity and limit have existed coherently for a long time.
 
  • #5
Since mathematics is by nature picky in the usage of language, I'm going to be picky about some of your statements.
Frank Peters said:
For example, a series x0+x1+x3+... is not considered to be a literal infinite sum with infinite terms but only the limiting value of an arbitrarily large number of terms.
There is a term for every natural number n. There are infinitely many natural numbers. That is, the set of natural numbers is recognized to be infinite, and an "infinite set" is a well-defined thing. We are perfectly happy with the idea that some sets are infinite and some are not.

What you've picked up is that "infinity" is not a real number. So we don't for instance define 1/0 but we can define the limit of ##1/a_n## as ##n \rightarrow \infty## and we may have that ##a_n \rightarrow 0##, and when we define that, everything in the definition is a real, finite number. We define the limit as a trend as n gets large but is always finite. We don't talk about the value "at" infinity.

And so the value of that sum is defined in terms of a limit. We define a partial sum as a sum of a finite number of terms, and we analyze what happens as the number of terms in the partial sums gets larger and larger, but remains finite.

Frank Peters said:
In other words, an completed infinity makes no sense in the concept of limit.
I don't know if I'd say "makes no sense". But I would say that the definitions are careful to only talk about what is happening with real numbers, which are by nature finite.

It doesn't have to be that way. You can define a rigorous mathematics where ##\infty## and ##-\infty## are added to the set of numbers. In that case it's called the "extended reals".

Frank Peters said:
However, the notion of infinity introduced by Georg Cantot does admit completed infinities. In Cantor's ideas, infinity does indeed exist an an actual quantity, and there are even a hierarchy of infinities.

No, in Cantor's ideas, sets are infinite. He didn't claim any real numbers are.

Frank Peters said:
How are these two seemingly opposed viewpoints reconciled?
If we cannot define an actual sum of infinite terms because infinity has been replaced by the limit concept, how can we admit the actual infinities defined by Cantor?

We can define an actual set of infinite terms, using Cantor's ideas. There is one term as I said for every natural number. We can define a bijection between the set of natural numbers and the set of terms. Therefore the set of terms has the same cardinality as the set of natural numbers.

And we can define the sum of those terms in terms of finite things.

Real numbers are finite. Sets can be infinite, including the set of real numbers. There is no contradiction between those things.

In an infinite sum, each term is finite. The number of terms is infinite. The sum of the terms is defined as a limit, in terms of finite sums of terms (partial sums). The set of partial sums is infinite, but each individual partial sum is finite.
 
  • Like
Likes FactChecker and Mark44
  • #6
Frank Peters said:
In other words, an completed infinity makes no sense in the concept of limit.

However, the notion of infinity introduced by Georg Cantor does admit completed infinities. In Cantor's ideas, infinity does indeed exist an an actual quantity, and there are even a hierarchy of infinities.
One thing is that Cantor's notion of infinite doesn't seem to be required to do much of "usual" mathematics. Apparently, there has been much work on it. Obviously trying to pursue/understand the exact detail (which I don't know very well) requires time commitment ... (not to mention that there are good number of variations on this). But still, I can include a number of pointers if someone is interested.

For example, it seems to be generally favoured (apparently with good reasons) that FLT is provable in PA. You can search for it and you will find good number of links.

====================

One thing though that is rarely talked about and, I feel, "might" be a point of concern. Consider the following proposition:
p: "There is no bijection between ℕ and ℝ"

Now one of the problems that I feel is that when we conclude (in ZFC) that:
q: "There is a bijection between ℝ and ω1"

The jump from p to q just seems a bit too much to me. I don't know whether it leads to some kind of actual "syntactic" issues or not though. Now it seems that some mathematicians do believe that ω1 shouldn't be considered a set (ref. if needed). So there seem to be two different conceptual lines of thinking here.

====================

And even the plausibility that ZFC is incorrect about some number theory statements (more specifically, incorrect about halting of some programs) is also expressed sometimes (ref. if needed). Note that this can also imply ~con(ZFC) (see next sentence). But even if one is wrong about halting and it is detectable via purely finite calculations (in the sense that we say a program loops when it actually halts), it might not be possible to detect it in any reasonable time scale (notably this also doesn't cover consistency doesn't imply soundness issue anyway).

For example, consider the abstract "possibility" that some statement (with comparable description length to FLT) is incorrect (but we consider it to be correct). If we express it as a reasonably small program (say around 100 lines), then in the "worst-case scenario" we would have to wait till a time-scale BB(100) to find out that the statement was actually wrong.

====================

Regarding my own opinion about this, I think something like con(PA) is true (because of its proof). If we find a similar proof for con(ZFC) ... after enough verification ... that would decisively settle its consistency at least. But ofc people who are expert on this say that this seems to be very far away (ref. if needed). But I don't really know. This is just what I have read.

There is something important (with regards to this topic) that I have quite recently learned. Consider the following two problems:
A-- There is a "path of natural notations" below ωCK
B-- con(ZFC)
Of course both are very old problems (from a purely mechanical viewpoint, one is a conceptual "problem" ... if it is one ... and the other is a syntactic problem). A is closely related to "natural notations" problem and it seems that Godel has explicitly mentioned (will describe the specific quote if someone is interested) both A and its related problem (I read this about an year ago and mentioned this in one of threads I made here).

Now what I have learned quite recently (based on some discussion on mathSE ... will provide link if someone is interested), about a month ago, is that if we consider the following possibilities/combinations:
p1-- A is not a "real" problem and B is true
p2-- A is not a "real" problem and B is false
p3-- A is a real problem (with a solution) and B is true
p4-- A is a real problem (with a solution) and B is false

Then the possibility p3 is unlikely (but still possible apriori). The (informal) reason is that, for p3 to exist, any method for A would quite likely somehow have to draw a "boundary line" at identifying ωCK ... and failing after that (still apriori possible but hard to see for me). Otherwise, without a distinguishing boundary line, such a method just seems to show that ω1 should not be considered a set.
And the sound of it does appear too fictional/fantastic admittedly. Possibly that also (partly) explains the pessimism around problem A?

====================

P.S.
As I have mentioned before, I had tried A (without even realising that I was trying the same problem ... because I wasn't even aware of existence of absurd recursive notations at that time) about 5 years ago. But after realising that the methods at that time didn't work, I didn't think about it again until 2 years ago. Now after a break of many months, I finally had the time to look at my method (which I had thought of an year ago) again (in last 2 months).

In hindsight, in my own approach (which didn't really work) for A, if they did work hypothetically, possibility p4 would have existed instead of p3. This is also true for my current approach (and the current specific method might be the last one I try ... since I can only think of few potentially meaningful modifications).
In a way, this does bring down my enthusiasm quite a bit (since I wasn't aware of this implication until a month ago). I have never heard of conception of ω1 not being a set bringing up a purely syntactic issue. Since I had finally time to look upon the current method in last two months, it does work better than I expected. Since the underlying method is concrete (and fully specified) I probably need to test it more.

Currently I would rate the optimism level regarding the working of this specific method at 5% (part of the reason I am assessing it low is because possibility p3 doesn't seem to exist in this method). In a timeline of one year (if I do keep working on it) I think I can get a very good idea ... either it comes down to 0% (95% chance?) or goes up by around 30--60% (5% chance?).
 
Last edited:
  • #7
RPinPA said:
We define the limit as a trend as n gets large but is always finite. We don't talk about the value "at" infinity.

And so the value of that sum is defined in terms of a limit. We define a partial sum as a sum of a finite number of terms, and we analyze what happens as the number of terms in the partial sums gets larger and larger, but remains finite.
...
In an infinite sum, each term is finite. The number of terms is infinite. The sum of the terms is defined as a limit, in terms of finite sums of terms (partial sums). The set of partial sums is infinite, but each individual partial sum is finite.

You seem to be saying two different things here. But mathematic does not admit infinite sums, or an actual infinite series. Such things are always defined in terms of a limit.

However, post-Cantor, it seems that infinite sums are now realizable. We should be able to talk about a one-to-one correspondence between the terms of a convergent series and the natural numbers, which would mean that after aleph-null number of terms the series does actually EQUAL the limit.

Yet conventional mathematics says we can't talk about an actual "infinte" series but only a series that can become "arbitrarily large."

To me, in my admitted ignorance of the complete subject, it seems like an extreme incompatibility.
 
  • #8
Frank Peters said:
You seem to be saying two different things here. But mathematic does not admit infinite sums, or an actual infinite series. Such things are always defined in terms of a limit.

However, post-Cantor, it seems that infinite sums are now realizable. We should be able to talk about a one-to-one correspondence between the terms of a convergent series and the natural numbers, which would mean that after aleph-null number of terms the series does actually EQUAL the limit.

Yet conventional mathematics says we can't talk about an actual "infinte" series but only a series that can become "arbitrarily large."

To me, in my admitted ignorance of the complete subject, it seems like an extreme incompatibility.

Cantorian set theory does allow us to talk about infinite objects, but it does not give any meaning to the concept of an infinite sum, other than the limit of finite sums. If you have a collection of reals ##r_1, r_2, ...##, set theory allows us to group them all into a single infinite set. But it doesn't give any meaning to the sum of that set (except in the sense of limits).
 
  • #9
How could mathematics NOT talk about infinite sets when there are so many of them (integers, real numbers, power sets)? And if one wants to talk about them, there must be some way of discussing infinity and different amounts of infinity. That has all been accomplished with great mathematical rigor. And given infinite sets, the concept of limits and cluster points can be studied. @Frank Peters should accept this and learn about it.
 
  • #10
Frank Peters said:
You seem to be saying two different things here. But mathematic does not admit infinite sums, or an actual infinite series. Such things are always defined in terms of a limit.
No, neither of these is true. Please provide a citation of some mathematician who says this.
There are infinite series all over the place, such as this infinite series for ##e^x##: ##\sum_{n = 0}^\infty \frac {x^n}{n!}##. This series has an infinite number of terms, which makes it a sum with an infinite number of terms. One definition for ##e^x## is this series, not a limit.
There are many more examples such as this one.

Frank Peters said:
However, post-Cantor, it seems that infinite sums are now realizable. We should be able to talk about a one-to-one correspondence between the terms of a convergent series and the natural numbers, which would mean that after aleph-null number of terms the series does actually EQUAL the limit.
This is nonsense.
Having a one-to-one correspondence between the terms of a convergent series and the natural numbers is trivial and irrelevant. The summation notation, ##\sum_{k = 1}^\infty a_k = a_1 + a_2 + a_3 + \dots + a_k + \dots## clearly shows how each term maps to a positive integer.

What is relevant is whether the sequence of partial sums for the series has a limit; if so, the series converges. The series converges if the sequence ##S_n = \sum_{k = 1}^n a_k## has a limit.

Frank Peters said:
Yet conventional mathematics says we can't talk about an actual "infinte" series but only a series that can become "arbitrarily large."
To repeat what @FactChecker said, who says we can't talk about an actual infinite series? I've given one example of an "actual" infinite series, and can provide a ton more of them if you need more convincing.

If you are unable to back up your assertions about what "conventional mathematics" says about infinite series, I will lock this thread.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes FactChecker
  • #11
Frank Peters said:
Supposedly, infininity has been purged from mathematics.

I hope I am being clear. If not then let me know.

You aren't being mathematically clear. To precisely define what it means for a concept to be "purged from mathematics", you would have to give a mathematically precise definition of the concept.

The words "infinity" and "infinite" do not descibe unique mathematical concepts. They have different meanings in different contexts.
 
  • #12
Frank Peters said:
To me, in my admitted ignorance of the complete subject
Don't you think this might be a problem?
 

1. What is the concept of infinity?

The concept of infinity refers to the idea of something being without limits or boundaries. It is a mathematical concept that describes something as being endless or unbounded.

2. What is the significance of Cantor's work on transfinite numbers?

Georg Cantor's work on transfinite numbers revolutionized the study of infinity by providing a way to compare and classify different levels of infinity. His work showed that not all infinities are equal and introduced the concept of different sizes of infinity.

3. How does Cantor's diagonal argument support the existence of uncountable infinities?

Cantor's diagonal argument is a proof that shows that there are different levels of infinity by demonstrating that the set of real numbers is uncountable. This means that there are more real numbers than natural numbers, providing evidence for the existence of uncountable infinities.

4. How is the concept of infinity used in mathematics and science?

The concept of infinity is used in many areas of mathematics and science, including calculus, topology, and physics. It is also used in practical applications such as computer and data science, where infinite sets and limits are used to model and solve real-world problems.

5. Are there any limitations to the concept of infinity?

While the concept of infinity is essential in mathematics and science, it does have some limitations. For example, infinity cannot be used as a number in calculations, and not all infinities are equal. Additionally, the concept of infinity can be difficult to grasp and can lead to paradoxes and contradictions if not carefully defined and used.

Similar threads

  • General Math
Replies
5
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
938
Replies
1
Views
2K
  • General Math
Replies
4
Views
4K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
6
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
11
Views
3K
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
21
Views
2K
Back
Top