Evaluate this paper on the derivation of the Born rule

In summary, The paper discusses the Curie Wiess model of the quantum measurement process and how it can be used to derive the Born rule.
  • #176
Come on, the uncertainties in the value of ##\hbar## in the SI is really off-topic in a thread about the foundations of QT, and you have not given a clear explanation for your very bold claim that Born's rule, one of the very foundations of QT is invalid. You simply rename the formalism to take expectation values by not telling it taking the average given a probability distribution but something else, you don't clarify.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #177
vanhees71 said:
Born's rule, one of the very foundations of QT
As the paper under discussion in this thread shows (in conjunction with the analysis cited in my post #85) , it is not a necessary foundation for QT, since the authors give alternative foundations where it is not needed, but special instances of it are derived.
 
  • #178
Prathyush said:
I don't think any new postulate is required, I think it would only require a careful analysis of what we mean by measurement.

Have you studied Gleason:
http://kiko.fysik.su.se/en/thesis/helena-master.pdf

Weinberg is indeed correct - an extra assumption is required and since Gleason it's well known what that extra assumption is - its non-contextuality. There are a couple of others such as the strong principle of superposition but that's the main one.

When going through the theorem its so beautiful and elegant you are inclined to forget its implicit assumption - the measure is basis independent because basis are usually something you simply choose to make a problem easier - not of fundamental importance - but in this case it is. That it not to diminish Gleason - its one of my favorite QM results and I have created some versions of my own it fascinates me so much. But the assumption is there and can't be ignored.

Be very very careful with mathematical proofs of physical things - you must always look at what's really going on physically. My background is math - not physics and I just love some of these mathematical derivations. But while physics is written in the language of math its not math.

As another example see the post I did about Feynman's proof of Maxwell's equations. Dyson put a challenge out there - since it only uses classical assumptions where did the relativity of Maxwell's equations come from. There were a few conjectures put forward, some I agreed with but I wanted my own and came up with it. But someone else posting in that thread saw the rock bottom reason - it assumes C=1 which is only true in all frames relativistically - relativity in - relativity out.

It's the same reason for the Kaluza-Klein miracle that fascinated me in my GR days until I realized what was going on. The foundation of EM is U(1) gauge invariance ie the symmetry of a circle - but that's what you do in Kaluza-Kelin - you assume the equations are not dependent on the 5th dimension which physically was enforced by the 5th dimension being curled up in a circle - so we have EM in (ie U(1) invarience) so its no surprise you get EM out.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Auto-Didact
  • #179
A. Neumaier said:
As the paper under discussion in this thread shows (in conjunction with the analysis cited in my post #85) , it is not a necessary foundation for QT, since the authors give alternative foundations where it is not needed, but special instances of it are derived.
Already in the Abstract of the paper in #1 you can read
Finally the field induced by S on M, which
may take two opposite values with probabilities given by Born’s rule, drives A into its up or down
ferromagnetic phase. The overall final state involves the expected correlations between the result
registered in M and the state of S. The measurement is thus accounted for by standard quantum
statistical mechanics
and its specific features arise from the macroscopic size of the apparatus.
[emphasis mine]
 
  • #180
vanhees71 said:
Already in the Abstract of the paper in #1 you can read
Yes. They explicitly explain what they mean in the follow up paper, mentioned already in post #85:

A.E. Allahverdyan, R. Balian and T.M. Nieuwenhuizen,
A sub-ensemble theory of ideal quantum measurement processes,
Annals of Physics 376 (2017): 324-352.
https://arxiv.org/abs/1303.7257

They mean with standard quantum statistical mechanics the mathematical formalism, with a physical interpretation not based on Born's rule but on their alternative interpretive rules. Otherwise their derivation of Born's rule would be circular. The first of their interpretive rules effectively replaces Born's rule in their view of statistical mechanics. This rule is is precisely the thermal interpretation:

Allahverdyan Balian and Nieuwenhuizen said:
Interpretative principle 1. If the q-variance of a macroscopic observable is negligible in relative size its q-expectation value is identified with the value of the corresponding macroscopic physical variable, even for an individual system.
 
  • #181
But isn't standard QT(not interpretational) that in the macroscopic limit the expectation value and the Born rule are equivalent, and one can use either one to derive the other, and therefore eithe one can be used as starting postulate?
 
Last edited:
  • #182
Yes, but they talk in the usual probabilistic language, and I've given this explanation for the classicality of many macroscopic observables in the very beginning of this thread. The short paper is a very nice demonstration of how QT is consistent in describing the object and measurement apparatus, which is macroscopic, quantum mechanically. It does not deny or disprove standard quantum theory and/or Born's rule!
 
  • #183
RockyMarciano said:
But isn't standard QT(not interpretational) that in the macroscopic limit the expectation value and the Born rule are equivalent, and one can use either one to derive the other, and therefore eithe one can be used as stariting postulate?
Well, it's not so obvious that under any circumstances all macroscopic systems behave classically, and indeed there are examples, where this is not the case, e.g., superfluidity, BECs, superconductivity, etc. are examples where you have specific quantum behavior of macroscopic systems.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #184
vanhees71 said:
Yes, but they talk in the usual probabilistic language, and I've given this explanation for the classicality of many macroscopic observables in the very beginning of this thread. The short paper is a very nice demonstration of how QT is consistent in describing the object and measurement apparatus, which is macroscopic, quantum mechanically. It does not deny or disprove standard quantum theory and/or Born's rule!
This is my point in that post. Regardless of the shortcomings of the Born rule, I don't think Neumaier's foundational attack to Born's rule from within the theory is possible.
 
  • #185
RockyMarciano said:
But isn't standard QT(not interpretational) that in the macroscopic limit the expectation value and the Born rule are equivalent, and one can use either one to derive the other, and therefore either one can be used as starting postulate?
They are not equivalent.

One can never derive from a rule that only applies to many repeated measurements anything that applies to a single measurement. Thus Born's rule (which is of the first kind) cannot imply the interpretive rule 1 of the authors of the paper under discussion, which is of the second kind. And to go from the second to the first (where it is possible at all) is a highly nontrivial matter since it requires to define the complete measurement process in terms of statistical mechanics. This is the reason why the work of Allahverdyan, Balian, and Nieuwenhuizen is both very relevant and a lot of detailed work.

vanhees71 said:
but they talk in the usual probabilistic language,
Only because it is difficult to avoid using this language. But they don't regard Born's rule as part of the foundation of quantum theory.

Apparently because they were criticized of circularity, they spelled out in the paper mentioned in #85 and #180 in detail which interpretation they want their work to be seen in.

There they deliberately introduced the distinction q-expectation value, q-probability, q-variance, etc. to emphasize that in the statistical mechanics calculus they don't assume the usual probabilities but only the formal quantities with the same names.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #186
Sure, in "axiomatic" formulations you can rename things as much as you like without changing the mathematical "universe". When it comes to physics, it's of course a different thing. Then you have to relate the theory to what's done in the lab, and I don't see anything in the short paper that contradicts standard QT in this respect, particularly not Born's rule. To the contrary, finally they show that the QT formalism within their simple example is compatible with what's measured, including the QT description of the macroscopic measurement apparatus + heat bath ("environment").
 
  • #187
Vanhees71, can you comment in the other thread. I know you have said you have unwatched, but I think what is been discussed is very important. Thank you.
 
  • #188
A. Neumaier said:
They are not equivalent.

One can never derive from a rule that only applies to many repeated measurements anything that applies to a single measurement.
I don't know why you insist on this. It is a basic assumption in QM and statisitical mechanics that macroscopic objects are made of large numbers of microscopic objects and that according to this single measurements done to macroscopic objects are FAPP equivalent to many repeated measurements of those microscopic constituents and in this sense to their expectation value when its uncertainty tends to zero.
 
  • #189
Yes, and if statistical QT weren't very successful in this, physicists would have tried to find a better theory since 1925.
 
  • #190
RockyMarciano said:
according to this single measurements done to macroscopic objects are FAPP equivalent to many repeated measurements of those microscopic constituents
No. They aren't. A measurement is something that is actually measured and yields a communicatable numerical result.
Thus many repeated experiments yield many recorded results. But a single macroscopic measurement yields only a single recorded result.
 
  • #191
You should visit the physics introductory lab! SCNR.
 
  • #192
A. Neumaier said:
No. They aren't. A measurement is something that is actually measured and yields a communicatable numerical result.
Thus many repeated experiments yield many recorded results. But a single macroscopic measurement yields only a single recorded result.
This distinction is irrelevant in the context of the QT formalism and statisitical mechanics, which you claim you are not questioning. Every single textbook on QT assumes that lab single measurements results in practice are useful precisely because one can imply that the single macroscopic measurement is a simultaneous measure of very many microscopic constituents in the same state, and that this is also equivalent to measuring repeatedly a single system.
Nothing about communicable or recorded results is in the QT and statisitcal mechanics math formalism.
 
  • #193
RockyMarciano said:
the single macroscopic measurement is a simultaneous measure of very many microscopic constituents in the same state,
How does the single number measure many things simultaneously?

The International vocabulary of basic and general terms in metrology (VIM) from ISO, the international organization for standardization, may be regarded as the authoritative document defining the concept of a measurement.
ISO said:
2.1
measurement
process of experimentally obtaining information about the magnitude of a quantity
NOTES
1 Measurement implies a measurement procedure, based on a theoretical model.
2 In practice, measurement presupposes a calibrated measuring system, possibly
subsequently verified.
Please tell me the measurement procedure used to measure each of these many microscopic constituents, and the measurement system with which these astronomically many measurements are carried out.
 
  • #194
Although I haven't attempted to follow all the details of the discussion here, I can't help feeling that it boils down to the issue I raised in post #3: that theoretical probability and statistical relative frequency are not necessarily best described as the same thing.
 
  • #195
mikeyork said:
Although I haven't attempted to follow all the details of the discussion here, I can't help feeling that it boils down to the issue I raised in post #3: that theoretical probability and statistical relative frequency are not necessarily the same thing.
It boils down to the point that theoretical expectation values and means over frequently repeated measurements are not the same thing, and that the former makes sense even for cases where no repetitions are made. But this is a hollow phrase only if one doesn't realize the implications of it for the measurement problem.
 
  • #196
A. Neumaier said:
It boils down to the point that theoretical expectation values and means over frequently repeated measurements are not the same thing, and that the former makes sense even for cases where no repetitions are made. But this is a hollow phrase only if one doesn't realize the implications of it for the measurement problem.
Well, a theoretical expectation value is a property of a distribution function is it not? So the issue becomes one of interpretation of the distribution.
 
  • #197
mikeyork said:
a theoretical expectation value is a property of a distribution function is it not?
No. Only for randon variables. But quantum operators are not random variables. There is no a priori reason why ##Tr\rho A## should have anything to do with measurement at all. Thus the connection, if any, must be postulated by an interpretation.
 
Last edited:
  • #198
A. Neumaier said:
No. Only for randon variables
So why call it an expectation value? AFAIK, the term is used exclusively for the first moment of a distribution function. Even a deterministic variable has a distribution function -- it's a delta-function.
 
  • #199
A. Neumaier said:
But quantum operators are not random variables.
They are not any sort of variable. They are operators.
 
  • #200
mikeyork said:
They are not any sort of variable. They are operators.
Yes, and They behave like random variables only under special circumstances, and like deterministic variables even more rarely.
mikeyork said:
So why call it an expectation value?
By analogy. Things are often called by names borrowed from a special case or an analogy.

Just as all sorts of formal objects are called vectors, not only little arrows. A state vector in quantum mechanics has nothing to do with a vector, except ithat it shares some of its formal properties.
 
  • #201
In still don't get your point. Every measurable variable has a distribution -- even deterministic variables. As I said, a deterministic variable is distributed with a delta-function. But for any actual measurement the theoretical distribution depends on the prior conditions. The prior conditions may give it a pre-determined value or not, as the case may be. And this is not dependent on frequency counting.

It seems to me the issue is simply one of specifying a rule for calculating the prior distribution function and the Born rule serves this purpose very neatly.
 
  • #202
mikeyork said:
Every measurable variable has a distribution -
But an operator is a priori a mathematical object and not a measurable variable and hence has no distribution. Thus its expectation value is a purely theoretical quantity unless you declare by an interpretation rule how it is related to measurement. The interpretation rule used by the authors of the paper under discussion is the one given by the thermal interpretation, which makes no reference to a distribution.

No distributions are needed (or even sensible) to interpret a single measurement. The measurement gives a result, and that's it. Distributions make sense only if you can repeat the measurement arbitrarily often.
 
  • #203
A. Neumaier said:
But an operator is a priori a mathematical object and not a measurable variable and hence has no distribution. Thus its expectation value is a purely theoretical quantity unless you declare by an interpretation rule how it is related to measurement.
I never claimed otherwise. I said any variable has a distribution function. That distribution function is what the Born rule provides.

No distributions are needed (or even sensible) to interpret a single measurement. The measurement gives a result, and that's it. Distributions make sense only if you can repeat the measurement arbitrarily often.
Here is where you have not grasped my point. A distribution function is a theoretical quantity derived from a theoretical concept of probability that applies directly to any single measurement regardless of whether you might (or could) count frequencies.

It seems to me you have fallen into the fallacy of assuming a distribution function implies a statistical distribution. But no actual statistical distribution is required. See my post #3 which was all about not confusing probability with statistics.
 
  • #204
mikeyork said:
I said any variable has a distribution function.
But an operator is not a variable.

A non-normal operator such as ##A=p+iq## has not even in principle a distribution function (since measuring ##A## would mean measuring ##p## and ##q##), though its expectation ##\langle A\rangle:=Tr \rho A## is well-defined for every state ##\rho##!
 
  • #205
A. Neumaier said:
But an operator is not a variable.
Does a measurement measure an operator or a variable? Do we measure ##<A>## or ##<a>##.

A non-normal operator such as ##A=p+iq## has not even in principle a distribution function (since measuring ##A## would mean measuring ##p## and ##q##), though its expectation ##\langle A\rangle:=Tr \rho A## is well-defined for every state ##\rho##!
The expectation ##\langle a\rangle## is a variable, not an operator and the variable ##a##, with values given by the eigenvalues of ##A##, has a distribution function ##|<a|\psi>|^2## for every state ##\psi##. That is the entire content of Born rule. It says nothing about operators; only variables. ##<a|\psi>## is what matters not ##A##.
 
  • #206
Sorry, perhaps I am missing something, but it seems to me that <A> says as much about A as it does about the density function, given they both appear on the RHS.
 
  • #207
Jilang said:
Sorry, perhaps I am missing something, but it seems to me that <A> says as much about A as it does about the density function, given they both appear on the RHS.
What are you referring to? We measure the expectation value of the observable variable ##a## (a scalar) not the operator ##A##. An operator means nothing until you operate on something.
 
  • #208
mikeyork said:
Does a measurement measure an operator or a variable? Do we measure ##<A>## or ##<a>##.
What is measured depends on the kind of measurement.

In a macroscopic measurement we measure ##<A>##, in a Born-type measurement we measure an eigenvalue of ##A##, in a photodetector we measure the presence of a photon in a beam.

If we measure temperature we measure a parameter occurring in the density operator.

Thus there are lots of possibilities.
 
  • #209
mikeyork said:
The expectation ##\langle a\rangle## is a variable
No, it is a number.
 
  • #210
A. Neumaier said:
In a macroscopic measurement we measure ##<A>##
What kind of macroscopic measurement do you have in mind? If we measure anything we get a number ##a_{macro}##. I have no idea what ##<A>## means except as shorthand for ##<\psi|A|\psi>## which is ##<a>##. You wrote ##<A> = Tr \rho A ## but ##Tr \rho A = <a>##. As far as I can see, ##<A>## (the "expectation value of an operator") may be a useful mathematical idea but is physically meaningless until you operate on something.
in a Born-type measurement we measure an eigenvalue of ##A##
Ok, but my point is that we don't measure ##<A>##. And whatever variable we do measure, it has a prior (i.e. conditional on state preparation) distribution function ##|<a|\psi>|^2##.
 

Similar threads

Replies
3
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
0
Views
236
  • General Discussion
2
Replies
54
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
48
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
47
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
11
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
49
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
42
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
944
Replies
13
Views
5K
Back
Top