Do bosons contradict basic probability laws?

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of mutually exclusive events and how they relate to probability theory. It is explained that for distinguishable particles, the probabilities of different distributions are mutually exclusive and add up to the total probability. However, for bosons which are indistinguishable, the probabilities of different distributions do not add up in the same way. This is because the probability distribution depends on the state in which the particles are prepared, and different states can have different probabilities for the same event. The conversation also touches on the idea that what can be measured in an experiment can affect the probabilities observed.
  • #36
What about the following calculation to keep it as simple as possible?
We have two non-interacting bosons in a 1-dimensional, infinitely deep well.
Both are in the same eigen-state.
What is the probability of finding both in the same half of the well.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
Philip Koeck said:
What about the following calculation to keep it as simple as possible?
We have two non-interacting bosons in a 1-dimensional, infinitely deep well.
Both are in the same eigen-state.
What is the probability of finding both in the same half of the well.
That's ##1/2##. I.e. ##1/4 + 1/4##.
 
  • Like
Likes Dr.AbeNikIanEdL
  • #38
PeroK said:
That's ##1/2##. I.e. ##1/4 + 1/4##.
I meant the probability for both being in the left half of the well.
 
  • #39
Well, that’s then the 1/4, of which there are two in @PeroK ’s post.
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK and Dale
  • #40
Dr.AbeNikIanEdL said:
Well, that’s then the 1/4, of which there are two in @PeroK ’s post.
That would be completely classical behaviour as for distinguishable particles. 1/4 for both in the left, 1/4 for both in the right and 1/2 for one in each.
 
  • #41
Philip Koeck said:
That would be completely classical behaviour as for distinguishable particles. 1/4 for both in the left, 1/4 for both in the right and 1/2 for one in each.

The difference being that, with indistinguishable particles you can not resolve the last case into 1/4 for “1st left 2nd right” and 1/4 for “1st right 2nd left”. As I said a few times now, nothing particularly QM related is happening in your question.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC
  • #42
OK, first of all, I literally learned what boson/fermion statistics are like 3 days ago after off handedly reading the relevant section in Shankar, so I only have the faintest idea of what I'm talking about, so take it with a massive grain of salt, but I think I understand what confused you. Let me try to figure out what exactly you are having trouble with.

Let's call the state where one boson is in the left department and one in the right as A11. The state where both bosons are in the left department is A20, and the one where both are in the second A02. We can do the same with top and bottom departments and call them B11, B02, and B20. We can assume (and that's probably what you have in mind) that these two are independent. You assumed that the 3 states are of equal probability, having some kind of "uniform" distribution in mind (although it probably does not exactly what you had in mind). You make the assumption that if you now separate it into 4 departments, thus getting 10 states, each of the 10 states should also have equal probability. This is wrong. The right way to do it with your assumption of 1/3 probability for each of the states in experiments A and B would be by multiplying the probabilities for these. So for example, for both particles in the left department you'd have P(A20)*P(B20)+P(A20)*P(B02)+P(A20)*P(B11)=1/3. Same for the right department. And then you'd be left with one more event, namely A11B11, which corresponds to one ball left one ball right, one ball up one ball down, and it also has a probability of 1/3. They all add up to 1 so nothing is wrong here. However while each of the states A20B20, A20B11, etc. corresponds to one state of the new space, so 2020, 2011,etc, the state A11B11 translates to FOUR separate states, namely 1010, 1001, 0101, 0110, so each of these states should have probabilities of 1/12.

This should not come as a surprise, it comes as a direct consequence of the way you chose your distribution to be. It is similar to how 7 is the most common result when you throw two dice instead of all results having equal weight. It's like making two dice so that each one is fair, but then being surprised when you throw them together and they don't give the same weight to each number. It doesn't have much to do with QM or bosons in particular, it has to do with statistics.
 
  • Like
Likes Dr.AbeNikIanEdL and PeroK
  • #43
Philip Koeck said:
That would be completely classical behaviour as for distinguishable particles. 1/4 for both in the left, 1/4 for both in the right and 1/2 for one in each.

It's not completely classical behaviour, as there is no classical analogue to the spatial wave-function and the distribution of position measurements would be non-classical. It's just that we have a symmetry about the centre of the box. Identical bosons in the same eigenstate behave the same as distinguishable bosons for the reason that the simple product wave-function is allowed, as it is symmetric.

If we choose different eigenstates (##a## and ##b##) for the two particles, there will be a difference because we have to symmetrize the wave-function for the indistinguishable case:
$$\psi(x_1, x_2) = \frac 1 {\sqrt 2}(\psi_a(x_1)\psi_b(x_2) + \psi_b(x_1)\psi_a(x_2))$$
The exchange forces are a direct result purely of this symmetrization requirement. Or, in the case of fermions, the anti-symmetrization requirement.

That said, I think we have got side-tracked onto "particles in a box" scenarios, that are possibly not relevant to your paper that deals with discrete quantum states. Maybe the particles in a box is the continuum limit of this, with the discrete states becoming a continuum of position eigenstates and supposing a uniform spatial distribution (which can only exist instantaneously in any case). But, to be honest, I'm not sure about that.
 
Last edited:
  • Love
Likes AndreasC
  • #44
Philip Koeck said:
All wave functions in an infinitely deep well have a symmetric absolute square, so the probability of finding 1 particle in one half of the well should be 1/2. I don't see any contradiction with my assumptions.
Cool, but in that case the probabilities wouldn't be evenly split at 1/3 for each state. It would be 1/2 for the state S (one particle in side A and one on side B), and 1/4 for each of the two others. I'm going to "pretend" like we're not talking about an actual box with particles inside but for some abstract configuration where we have two discreet possible states. The end result is the same thing if you have a continuous box with a symmetric wavefunction for each of the particles, except the entire methodology I am following here would be completely stupid because in that case, there is not a single state that corresponds to being found in one of the two departments, but rather an infinite collection of states (so you'd also have similar results for fermions, whereas here you'd get that it is impossible for both fermions to be in the same department), and you'd have to do something significantly different and slightly more complex to do what I am trying to do here so aaaaaaaanyways.

To see this, you can form the space of states from the wavefunctions you started with by means of outer product. For each particle, the state will be:
$$ \ket{\psi} = \frac{\ket{A}+\ket{B}}{\sqrt{2}} $$
Where A represents finding the particle in department A and B... Well you get the idea.
Now we can combine the two and get the wavefunction for both particles:

$$ \ket{\psi_{1}\psi_{2}} = \ket{\psi_1} \otimes \ \ket{\psi_2} = (\frac{\ket{A}+\ket{B}}{\sqrt{2}}) \otimes (\frac{\ket{A}+\ket{B}}{\sqrt{2}})$$

If you work that out, it gives us the following:
$$ \ket{\psi_{1}\psi_{2}} = \frac{1}{2}(\ket{A}\otimes\ket{A}+\ket{B}\otimes\ket{B}+\ket{A}\otimes\ket{B}+\ket{B}\otimes\ket{A}) $$

But now we have to bear in mind that since the particles are identical, there are only 3 states, namely ## \ket{AA} ##, ## \ket{BB} ## and ## \ket{S} ##. The first two are self explanatory, the third is the state where one particle (it doesn't matter which!) is in A, the other is in B. Let's see what exactly these correspond to:
$$ \ket{AA} = \ket{A}\otimes\ket{A} $$
$$ \ket{BB} = \ket{B}\otimes\ket{B} $$
Alright, these were obvious enough, but the particles are identical and they are bosons, so we have to symmetrize the third state:
$$ \ket{S} = \frac{\ket{A}\otimes\ket{B}+\ket{B}\otimes\ket{A}}{\sqrt{2}} $$

Now we can rewrite the state of the system:
$$ \ket{\psi_{1}\psi_{2}} = \frac{1}{2}\ket{AA}+\frac{1}{2}\ket{BB}+\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}\ket{S}$$

Notice how the coefficients for AA and BB are 1/2, while for S it is 1/√2. These correspond to probabilities of 1/4, 1/4 and 1/2 respectively. So as you can see a "uniform" distribution for each boson doesn't give you the same probabilities for all 3 states. It's almost exactly what you would expect for two balls, except you can't split the state S into two states, AB and BA. That's the sole difference here. If you had fermions instead it would be a bit different because you can't have them both in one state. Of course, as I explained earlier this would not really apply the same way in the example of a continuous box.

Anyways, there is a VERY high chance I am making some mistake here because as I mentioned earlier, I learned this stuff only around 3 days ago so if I am, I'd appreciate if you corrected me. It was nice though that I was given the opportunity to think about these things a bit more because I feel more confident in my understanding now.
 
  • Informative
  • Like
Likes PeroK and Dale
  • #45
AndreasC said:
.
.
Now we can rewrite the state of the system:
$$ \ket{\psi_{1}\psi_{2}} = \frac{1}{2}\ket{AA}+\frac{1}{2}\ket{BB}+\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}\ket{S}$$

Notice how the coefficients for AA and BB are 1/2, while for S it is 1/√2. These correspond to probabilities of 1/4, 1/4 and 1/2 respectively. So as you can see a "uniform" distribution for each boson doesn't give you the same probabilities for all 3 states. It's almost exactly what you would expect for two balls, except you can't split the state S into two states, AB and BA. That's the sole difference here. If you had fermions instead it would be a bit different because you can't have them both in one state. Of course, as I explained earlier this would not really apply the same way in the example of a continuous box.
If I understand your post correctly you are saying that for a 2-state system the 3 possible distributions of 2 bosons don't all have the same probability of 1/3 and for a 4 state system the 10 possible distributions don't all have probability 10, all based on QM-calculations. Clearly if you are right my original problem disappears.
In the microcanonical derivation of BE-statistics, however, there is an implicit assumption, I think, that all distributions of n bosons among g states are equally likely (see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bose–Einstein_statistics or my own texts on ResearchGate).
What's going on here? Is there a real discrepancy between QM and statistical physics?
 
  • #46
Hi, every one.
Do you know Probability Axioms (by Kolmogorov) ?

Event : E⊆Ω   Probability : Pr(E)
Axiom 1 0≦Pr(E)≦1
Axiom 2 Pr(Ω)=1
Axiom 3 Ei∩Ej=∅ (i≠j)
⇒ Pr(E1∪E2∪・・・∪En)=Pr(E1)+Pr(E2)+ ・・・+Pr(En)

Two particles in the container.
[left, right] (left up, left low, right up, right low)

Ω={[2,0],[1,1],[0,2]}
Ω={(2,0,0,0),(1,1,0,0),(0,2,0,0),
(1,0,1,0),(1,0,0,1),(0,1,1,0),(0,1,0,1),
(0,0,2,0),(0,0,1,1),(0,0,0,2)}

Method A:Two particles are distinguishable.
→Pr({[2,0]})=Pr({[0,2]}), Pr({1,1]})=2Pr({[2,0]})
Pr({(2,0,0,0)})=Pr({(0,2,0,0)})=Pr({(0,0,2,0)})=Pr({(0,0,0,2)}),
Pr({(1,1,0,0)})=Pr({(1,0,1,0)})=Pr({(1,0,0,1)})=Pr({(0,1,1,0)})
=Pr({(0,1,0,1)})=Pr({(0,0,1,1)})=2Pr({(2,0,0,0)})
Method B:Two particles are indistinguishable.
→Pr({[2,0]})=Pr({[0,2]}), Pr({1,1]})=Pr({[2,0]})
Pr({(2,0,0,0)})=Pr({(0,2,0,0)})=Pr({(0,0,2,0)})=Pr({(0,0,0,2)})
=Pr({(1,1,0,0)})=Pr({(1,0,1,0)})=Pr({(1,0,0,1)})=Pr({(0,1,1,0)})
=Pr({(0,1,0,1)})=Pr({(0,0,1,1)})

By using Method A,
1=Pr(Ω)=4Pr({[2,0]}) ∴Pr({[2,0]})=1/4
1=Pr(Ω)=16Pr({(2,0,0,0)}) ∴Pr({(2,0,0,0)})=1/16
Accordingly
Pr({(2,0,0,0)})+Pr({(1,1,0,0)})+Pr({(0,2,0,0)})=1/4
By the way,
{[2,0]}={(2,0,0,0)}+{(1,1,0,0)}+{(0,2,0,0)}
And
Pr({[2,0]})= Pr({(2,0,0,0)})+Pr({(1,1,0,0)})+Pr({(0,2,0,0)})
It fits Axom 3.

By using Method B,
1=Pr(Ω)=3Pr({[2,0]}) ∴Pr({[2,0]})=1/3
1=Pr(Ω)=10Pr({(2,0,0,0)}) ∴Pr({(2,0,0,0)})=1/10
Accordingly
Pr({(2,0,0,0)})+Pr({(1,1,0,0)})+Pr({(0,2,0,0)})=3/10
By the way,
{[2,0]}={(2,0,0,0)}+{(1,1,0,0)}+{(0,2,0,0)}
But
Pr({[2,0]})≠ Pr({(2,0,0,0)})+Pr({(1,1,0,0)})+Pr({(0,2,0,0)})
It doesn't fit Axom 3.

The elementary particles are mysterious.
The observation result may change for one's heart.
But, this is a discussion of the mathematics purely.
 
  • #47
Philip Koeck said:
If I understand your post correctly you are saying that for a 2-state system the 3 possible distributions of 2 bosons don't all have the same probability of 1/3 and for a 4 state system the 10 possible distributions don't all have probability 10, all based on QM-calculations. Clearly if you are right my original problem disappears.
In the microcanonical derivation of BE-statistics, however, there is an implicit assumption, I think, that all distributions of n bosons among g states are equally likely (see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bose–Einstein_statistics or my own texts on ResearchGate).
What's going on here? Is there a real discrepancy between QM and statistical physics?
That Wikipedia page is talking about the distribution of energy states in thermodynamic equilibrium. That's a different scenario from the one you are looking at.
 
  • #48
PeroK said:
That Wikipedia page is talking about the distribution of energy states in thermodynamic equilibrium. That's a different scenario from the one you are looking at.
As I read it, it's talking about distributions of particles among states with the same energy. This is then extended to several energy levels. The most likely distribution of particles among energy levels is simply found by looking for the maximum number of distributions given the constraints of total energy and particle number.
Interestingly there is no discussion of different probabilities for different distributions.
 
  • #49
Philip Koeck said:
As I read it, it's talking about distributions of particles among states with the same energy. This is then extended to several energy levels. The most likely distribution of particles among energy levels is simply found by looking for the maximum number of distributions given the constraints of total energy and particle number.
Interestingly there is no discussion of different probabilities for different distributions.
You must be able to see your problem. If you simply look for particles in different positions you are dealing with a common wave-function or common distribution of states. That doesn't change so that all options become equally likely, depending on what you want to look for. I.e. if you decide notionally to subdivide the box into thirds, that doesn't create three "states". Particle measurements are indepenent of any notional subdivisions. Your false assumption is that by notionally deciding the box is divided into thirds, you have created three possible states.

If, however, you physically subdivide the system into thirds, then you have a different system from the original. And, if you allow the system to reach equilibrium, you may use the Bose-Einstein statistics.

In other words, the change from a possible two to a possible three states must be a real physical change. Not just an arbitrary decision to categorise the results of where you find particles when you look for them.
 
  • Informative
Likes AndreasC
  • #50
I believe you are still making the mistake of conflating the "states" (again, can't really split AB and BA) AA, BB, AB and BA being of equal probability with the states AA, BB and S being of equal probability.

EDIT: Nah, I believe PeroK's reply is probably the correct take.
 
  • #51
PeroK said:
In other words, the change from a possible two to a possible three states must be a real physical change. Not just an arbitrary decision to categorise the results of where you find particles when you look for them.
PS to see the problem more clearly, imagine you gather the data first. Then you analyse it. You have only one set of data and it cannot meet all your equally likely criteria.

If, however, you physically subdivide the box, then you can only obtain data for that one configuration. And, there is no need for that configuration to be compatible in with a different physical configuration.
 
  • #52
Let's take a close look at the derivation on Wikipedia. They just give an expression for the number of actually different distributions of n particles among g states on the same energy level. Clearly particle 1 in state 1 and 2 in 2 is the same as 1 in 2 and 2 in 1, since they are bosons. They do this for each energy level.
Then they just look for the distribution of particles among energy levels with the largest total number of distributions among states with fixed total energy and particle number. This is reported as the most likely distribution, without considering that different distributions of particles among states might have different probabilities. Isn't that right?
 
  • #53
To understand a bit better what I believe Pero is saying, think of fermions. Let's say we have two identical electrons in a box. Let's call the state of them being in the box A. So they're both in state A. Except that's impossible. Now let's say we call the left part of the box A and the right B. Well, suddenly they can both be in the box by one being in state A and the other in B. What's happening? Well, neither A or B are real states. Instead, an infinite number of states can correspond to the particle being found in the box or in the left department or in the right department. There has to be some extra physical change to really separate the system into 2 distinguishable states, and the whole discussion is a bit confusing because we're jumping back and forth from a continuous particle in a box example to distinguishable states to thermodynamic equilibrium etc.
 
  • Like
Likes Dr.AbeNikIanEdL and PeroK
  • #54
That

AndreasC said:
the whole discussion is a bit confusing because we're jumping back and forth from a continuous particle in a box example to distinguishable states to thermodynamic equilibrium etc.
@Philip Koeck , you seem to just take isolated blocks from one of those scenarios and assume that it is true in a completely different one, just because one can broadly headline both with "has something to do with QM". What is the scenario we are actually supposed to discuss?

Particles in a box, prepared in a state that yet has to be specified?
If yes, please specify that state.

Particles in a system with n discrete states, distributed according to a distribution that yet has to be specified?
If yes, please specify that distribution.

Particles in a system with n discrete states, distributed according to thermal equilibrium?
If yes, please state that.
 
  • #55
Dr.AbeNikIanEdL said:
That

@Philip Koeck , you seem to just take isolated blocks from one of those scenarios and assume that it is true in a completely different one, just because one can broadly headline both with "has something to do with QM". What is the scenario we are actually supposed to discuss?

Particles in a box, prepared in a state that yet has to be specified?
If yes, please specify that state.

Particles in a system with n discrete states, distributed according to a distribution that yet has to be specified?
If yes, please specify that distribution.

Particles in a system with n discrete states, distributed according to thermal equilibrium?
If yes, please state that.
I'll go for the last one. I think that fits the discussion of BE-statistics best.
 
  • #56
In that case the last few answers apply. What you actually want to have is something like a system with 2 discrete states, you then make an actual physical change to that system so that it has 4 discrete states afterwards. You then wait until thermal equilibrium is reached again. After this, probabilities have changed, which should be expected since you changed the system, and the 2 states you started with are not occupied in the same way as before.
 
  • Like
Likes Philip Koeck and PeroK
  • #57
PeroK said:
PS to see the problem more clearly, imagine you gather the data first. Then you analyse it. You have only one set of data and it cannot meet all your equally likely criteria.

If, however, you physically subdivide the box, then you can only obtain data for that one configuration. And, there is no need for that configuration to be compatible in with a different physical configuration.
Let's turn the problem around:
I have 2 bosons and 4 states with the same energy. According to the assumptions implicit in the derivation of BE-statistics the 10 possible distributions all have the same probability of 1/10.
If I carry out a series of measurements I'll find that both bosons are in the states 1 or 2 with a probability of 3/10 (or 3/10ths of the time).
Now I do a second set of measurements with a less accurate instrument. I cannot say whether a particle is in state 1 or 2, and likewise I cannot say whether a particle is in state 3 or 4. Effectively the instrument only distinguishes between 2 states.
Should I now get the probability 1/3 for finding both bosons in states 1 or 2 (which I can't tell apart) or should I get 3/10.
Notice that I haven't changed the physics of the system. I've only changed the accuracy of my measurement.
 
  • #58
If you don't change the system, the probability for a given state to find both bosons in state 1 or 2 does not change. Whether you actually resolve between state 1 and 2 does not matter for this.
 
  • Like
Likes Philip Koeck
  • #59
Philip Koeck said:
Let's turn the problem around:
I have 2 bosons and 4 states with the same energy. According to the assumptions implicit in the derivation of BE-statistics the 10 possible distributions all have the same probability of 1/10.
If I carry out a series of measurements I'll find that both bosons are in the states 1 or 2 with a probability of 3/10 (or 3/10ths of the time).
Now I do a second set of measurements with a less accurate instrument. I cannot say whether a particle is in state 1 or 2, and likewise I cannot say whether a particle is in state 3 or 4. Effectively the instrument only distinguishes between 2 states.
Should I now get the probability 1/3 for finding both bosons in states 1 or 2 (which I can't tell apart) or should I get 3/10.
Notice that I haven't changed the physics of the system. I've only changed the accuracy of my measurement.
This is going off at a tangent now. To take an example. Suppose we have 9 states that all have similar energies and one outlier. Let's say with equal probability. An accurate measurement might identify all ten states and the outlier would be found 1/10.

If we now have less sensitive equipment that cannot distinguish the nine states, then we still get the outlier only 1/10 and the amalgamation of the other states 9/10.
 
  • Like
Likes Philip Koeck
  • #60
I think I'm satisfied with the take home message of this discussion: States are real things and not a matter of how one groups them together or how accurately one can measure. What led to the original problem in my first post is that Kazu and I grouped states together and treated these groups as if they were physical states.
Thank you all very much for input.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC, PeroK and Dr.AbeNikIanEdL
  • #61
Philip Koeck said:
Summary:: The probabilities of mutually exclusive events are additive. For bosons this does not seem to be the case. How can we explain this?
...
How can we understand this?
Does it mean that different distributions of bosons in compartments are not mutually exclusive?
That would mean that there is some sort of overlap between the event of 2 bosons being in the upper compartment and the event of 1 being in the upper and 1 in the lower, somehow both distributions can exist at the same time.
I won't go into the probability math of this, I rather look at it physically rather than mathematically. And the way I picture bosons is that they are not mutually exclusive, several such particles can occupy the same space at the same time as each other. For example, the most common example of a boson is the photon. Within a given space and time, you can fit a nearly infinite number of photons in at the same time, and they don't interfere with each other. But with a fermion, that's not the case, there only one particle of a certain type can occupy the same time and space, due to the Pauli exclusion principle. The Pauli exclusion principle doesn't apply to the bosons, only to the fermions.

However, the amount of bosons you can fit into a certain space and time is not infinite (just nearly so, a very high number). The limit seems to be the Planck density, that is if you pack in the Planck energy's worth of bosons into a Planck volume of space, then the boson capacity is reached and you can't go any further, and a black hole is produced instead.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #62
bbbl67 said:
I won't go into the probability math of this, I rather look at it physically rather than mathematically. And the way I picture bosons is that they are not mutually exclusive, several such particles can occupy the same space at the same time as each other. For example, the most common example of a boson is the photon. Within a given space and time, you can fit a nearly infinite number of photons in at the same time, and they don't interfere with each other. But with a fermion, that's not the case, there only one particle of a certain type can occupy the same time and space, due to the Pauli exclusion principle. The Pauli exclusion principle doesn't apply to the bosons, only to the fermions.

However, the amount of bosons you can fit into a certain space and time is not infinite (just nearly so, a very high number). The limit seems to be the Planck density, that is if you pack in the Planck energy's worth of bosons into a Planck volume of space, then the boson capacity is reached and you can't go any further, and a black hole is produced instead.
I meant that the events are mutually exclusive. For example one event could be that there is 1 boson in state A and 1 boson in state B. Another event could be that there are 2 bosons in state A.
If these two events can't happen at the same time then they are mutually exclusive in the sense of probability theory, if I understand correctly.
I'm not completely convinced that this has to be true for bosons, but I don't want to make them weirder than they are.
 
  • #63
PeroK said:
Looking at what you've done, you got the same answer for distinguishable and indistinguishable fermions. That can't be correct, because identical fermions (or to be precise, fermions with a symmetric spin state, hence anti-symmetric spatial wave-function) have a repulsive exchange force, so would tend to be found further apart.
That's an interesting detail. I was also surprised.
In my derivation I don't use the concept of space. I just have two groups of states that I call "volumes".
Both distinguishable and indistinguishable fermions block the states they are in, so maybe one shouldn't expect any difference in their behaviour.
I'm not even sure whether distinguishable fermions correspond to anything real anyway.
 
  • #64
Philip Koeck said:
I'm not even sure whether distinguishable fermions correspond to anything real anyway.

Of course they do; consider, for example, an electron and a proton.
 
  • #65
Philip Koeck said:
Both distinguishable and indistinguishable fermions block the states they are in

If by "block" you are referring to the Pauli exclusion principle, that only applies to indistinguishable fermions. An electron and a proton would not "block" each other from being in the same state.
 
  • #66
PeterDonis said:
If by "block" you are referring to the Pauli exclusion principle, that only applies to indistinguishable fermions. An electron and a proton would not "block" each other from being in the same state.
In my derivations I always talk about identical particles even if they are distinguishable.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes PeroK
  • #67
Philip Koeck said:
In my derivations I always talk about identical particles even if they are distinguishable.

Then I'm not clear about what you mean by "identical" particles.
 
  • #68
PeterDonis said:
Then I'm not clear about what you mean by "identical" particles.
Identical simply means the same in all properties. Two large objects (maybe atom clusters) could be identical, but it's still possible to keep track of them and see which particle is where or in which state. So they are distinguishable.
Indistinguishable means that it's principally impossible to tell which of two particles is in state A and which is in state B. There is no measurement that would give you that information.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes PeroK
  • #69
Philip Koeck said:
Identical simply means the same in all properties.

It can't literally be "all properties" unless the state of the particle is not one of its properties. But perhaps you mean just all invariant properties like charge or magnitude of spin.
 
  • #70
Philip Koeck said:
Identical simply means the same in all properties. Two large objects (maybe atom clusters) could be identical, but it's still possible to keep track of them and see which particle is where or in which state. So they are distinguishable.

No, that's not true. The wavefunction is such that you can't tell which is which. Whatever this derivation of yours is, it's not quantum mechanics.

It's evident you don't know QM. That's fine. None of us know everything about everything. But maybe before coming here and telling su it's wrong it would be a good idea to learn what it says? It is probably also not a good idea to call this an A-level thread if you don't have a graduate-level background in QM.
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK

Similar threads

Replies
12
Views
759
Replies
3
Views
818
Replies
14
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
20
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
743
  • Precalculus Mathematics Homework Help
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
17
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
6
Views
1K
Back
Top