Can we violate Bell inequalities by giving up CFD?

In summary: I find it easier to think of a choice between locality or singular outcomes.The issue is that under certain assumptions, singular outcomes imply a choice between reality and locality. And the violation of Bell's inequality implies singular outcomes.If you don't want to give up reality, then you must give up locality. That is what Bell's theorem tells us. The fact that some people say it the other way around doesn't make it so.Note that the issue is not that 2 measurement events are connected. That is completely fine. The issue is that they are connected in a way that would require either superluminal communication or a violation of local causality. But both of those are ruled out by special relativity. This is what we mean
  • #36
Ilja said:
Giving up causality kills an important part of science - the search for realistic causal explanations of observed correlations.

You consider that an important part of science - others disagree.

For me its what Feynman says:


Thanks
Bill
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
bhobba said:
So? It uses a definition of CFD and locality and shows its violated by QM.
And therefore proves much less than proven by Bell, thus, not worth to be read.

rubi said:
There are no non-relativistic elements in relativistic quantum theories. Relativistic quantum theories carry a unitary representation of the Poincare group and this is all that is needed to call them perfectly relativistically covariant and it is also independent of the Heisenberg or Schrödinger picture. Observers that are moving at relative speed agree on all observable facts. This is really universally agreed upon by all serious physicists who understand relativistic quantum theory, which is the broad majority of the physics community.
Thanks for telling me that I'm not a serious physicist and don't understand relativistic quantum theory. If "observers that are moving at relative speed agree on all observable facts" is all you require for a "perfectly relativistically covariant" theory, you simply have different criteria for what it means. IMHO it means manifest Lorentz invariance of all elements of the theory, not only the final observable results. I have never seen such a thing in the Schrödinger picture, with consideration of a measurement process, but it will not be a problem for you to give me a reference for this, not? Or do I first have to become "serious"?

rubi said:
There is no need to give up causality. I don't see how you get the idea that one would have to do that. It is certainly wrong.
There is. Reichenbach's principle of common cause is, together with Einstein causality, all one needs to prove Bell's inequality. You may, of course, continue to name what remains if one rejects Reichenbach's common cause, but I don't think the sad remains deserve this name. The pure "signal locality" certainly does not deserve it.
rubi said:
The existence of a perfectly relativistically covariant theory that violates Bell's inequality proves that special relativity (which is a synonym for relativistic covariance) doesn't imply Bell's inequality.
No, it only means that one can give up causality essentially, by rejecting Reichenbach's principle of common cause, and continue to name the remains "causality" in such a theory without raising much protest. The tobacco industry will be happy if science will no longer search for causal explanations of observed correlations.
 
  • #38
bhobba said:
You consider that an important part of science - others disagree.
For me its what Feynman says:
Hm, I was unable to localize the disagreement. Instead, I feel nicely supported by his example of astrological influences near 3.20. Slightly reformulated, if it would be true, that the stars could effect something on Earth - which we would observe as a correlation - then all the physics would be wrong, because there is no mechanism - no causal explanation - which would allow to explain this influence.

So, Feynman seems to agree with me that the requirement that for correlations where should be a causal, realistic (even mechanical!) explanation is an important part of science. So important that a theory which does not provide such explanation would be wrong - at least in this example this was quite explicit.
 
  • #39
Ilja said:
Hm, I was unable to localize the disagreement.

If it disagrees with experiment then its wrong. In that one statement is the essence of science - not the search for realism.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #40
Ilja said:
Thanks for telling me that I'm not a serious physicist and don't understand relativistic quantum theory. If "observers that are moving at relative speed agree on all observable facts" is all you require for a "perfectly relativistically covariant" theory, you simply have different criteria for what it means. IMHO it means manifest Lorentz invariance of all elements of the theory, not only the final observable results. I have never seen such a thing in the Schrödinger picture, with consideration of a measurement process, but it will not be a problem for you to give me a reference for this, not? Or do I first have to become "serious"?
All elements of convential relativistic quantum theory are manifestly Lorentz invariant. Switching between the Schrödinger and Heisenberg picture is nothing more than the application of the time-translation operator, which exists, because we provably have unitary representations of the Poincare group, which includes time-translation operators (This can be verified by anyone who knows how to calculate commutators, so basically every undergraduate student of quantum mechanics). Almost every textbook on relativistic QM or QFT explains it (for example Weinberg vol. 1). (Being serious definitely helps.)

There is. Reichenbach's principle of common cause is, together with Einstein causality, all one needs to prove Bell's inequality. You may, of course, continue to name what remains if one rejects Reichenbach's common cause, but I don't think the sad remains deserve this name. The pure "signal locality" certainly does not deserve it.
It is well known that QM doesn't satisfy Bell's locality criterion ("Einstein causality"). That doesn't mean it is not causal. The cause for the correlations is of course that the quantum system has been prepared in a state that results in those correlations. If you prepare the system in a different state, you will not see the same correlations. This is a perfect cause and effect relationship. Bell's locality criterion is just too narrow and doesn't capture the meaning of the word causality adequately. So please don't force your personal definition of causality on everybody else.

Instead of continuously pointing to Reichenbach, you should maybe also consider Popper at some point.

No, it only means that one can give up causality essentially, by rejecting Reichenbach's principle of common cause, and continue to name the remains "causality" in such a theory without raising much protest. The tobacco industry will be happy if science will no longer search for causal explanations of observed correlations.
This is really just plain logic: A statement of the form "All X satisfy Y" can be disproven by giving an example of an X that doesn't satisfy Y.
 
  • Like
Likes andrewkirk and bhobba
  • #41
bhobba said:
If it disagrees with experiment then its wrong. In that one statement is the essence of science - not the search for realism.
If I would have to summarize the most important point of scientific methodology, I would use a similar formulation. So, no contradiction, only extremal simplification.

And, given that Feynman has not stopped after this first sentence, he thought some more things are worth to be said about science, not?

By the way, at 2.00 he gives another example about what would be scientific to say which contains an explanation of some phenomenon. He does not say "these are simply observations, not related to our theories, thus, science couldn't care less", but gives and explanation. At 2.48 he talks about extrasensory perception - which "cannot be explained by this". He notes that if it could be established that it exists, it would mean physics is incomplete, and it would be extremely interesting to physics.
 
  • #42
rubi said:
Instead of continuously pointing to Reichenbach, you should maybe also consider Popper at some point.
I was intrigued that at least half of Feynman's thoughts in that video were pure Popper. I would think of this as a case of 'great minds think alike' if not for the strange fact that Feynman was well-known to regard philosophy of science as useless ("Philosophy of science is about as useful to scientists as ornithology is to birds").

Popper wrote of falsifiability in 1934, when Feynman was only 16. Most probably Feynman was aware of Popper's ideas - although he may not have been aware that they belonged to Popper, or that Popper was a philosopher of science. Or maybe Feynman came upon them independently and later. I regard Feynman as a good philosopher as well as a brilliant scientist, notwithstanding his ostensible disdain for philosophy.
 
  • #43
andrewkirk said:
I regard Feynman as a good philosopher as well as a brilliant scientist, notwithstanding his ostensible disdain for philosophy.

He was.

Which makes his view on philosophy interesting - anti philosophy is also a philosophy.

Trouble with me is I agree with him - for me philosophy is mostly semantic waffle. Sorry - but I simply can't warm to it even though I gave it a fair go by starting a postgraduate certificate in it - although it turned out more a historical analysis of it rather than the ideas itself. It's simply not my bag.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #44
rubi said:
All elements of convential relativistic quantum theory are manifestly Lorentz invariant. Switching between the Schrödinger and Heisenberg picture is nothing more than the application of the time-translation operator, which exists, because we provably have unitary representations of the Poincare group, which includes time-translation operators (This can be verified by anyone who knows how to calculate commutators, so basically every undergraduate student of quantum mechanics). Almost every textbook on relativistic QM or QFT explains it (for example Weinberg vol. 1).
Reading for example Fulling, Aspects of Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime p.19, I have a slightly different impression.

"The Schrodinger formalism gives time a privileged role. The Heisenberg point of view permits t and the spatial coordinates to be treated on the same footing, hence permits a geometrically covariant formulation in keeping with the spirit of relativity theory." IOW, the Schrodinger formalism does not permit a manifestly covariant formulation, not? The note "As previously remarked, it is far from clear that a Schrodinger formulation should even make sense for a field system — especially with explicitly time-dependent field equations — because of the difficulty of constructing a Hamiltonian operator" seems also interesting.

rubi said:
It is well known that QM doesn't satisfy Bell's locality criterion ("Einstein causality"). That doesn't mean it is not causal. The cause for the correlations is of course that the quantum system has been prepared in a state that results in those correlations.
I know that if somebody insists on naming these poor remains "causality" it is hopeless to convince him, so be it.

rubi said:
Instead of continuously pointing to Reichenbach, you should maybe also consider Popper at some point.
I have no problem considering Popper. Popper tell's me that a theory which accepts Reichenbachs principle of common cause has a much greater predictive power, because it predicts zero correlation for everything which is not causally connected in the theory.
 
  • #45
Ilja said:
Reading for example Fulling, Aspects of Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime p.19, I have a slightly different impression.

"The Schrodinger formalism gives time a privileged role. The Heisenberg point of view permits t and the spatial coordinates to be treated on the same footing, hence permits a geometrically covariant formulation in keeping with the spirit of relativity theory." IOW, the Schrodinger formalism does not permit a manifestly covariant formulation, not?
Not. The Schrödinger formalism is perfectly equivalent to the Heisenberg formalism. You can rewrite any Lorentz covariant theory into a form that doesn't look Lorentz covariant on first sight. Even Maxwell's equations are usually presented in a form the hides the Lorentz covariance and "gives time a preferred role". That doesn't change the fact that they are Lorentz invariant, as can be seen by rewriting them in tensor notation and these formulations are equivalent. It is exactly the same thing for the Schrödinger and Heisenberg picture and it's absolutely trivial to prove the equivalence and it is done in every textbook.

The note "As previously remarked, it is far from clear that a Schrodinger formulation should even make sense for a field system — especially with explicitly time-dependent field equations — because of the difficulty of constructing a Hamiltonian operator" seems also interesting.
In QFT on CST, the situation is more difficult, since one doesn't have a representation of the Poincare group anymore (obviously, since general spacetimes are usually not Poincare invariant). Anyway, we don't need QFT on CST to prove the existence of a manifestly Lorentz covariant quantum theory. There are lots of trivial examples. Just consult Reed & Simon if you're looking for rigorous proofs.

I know that if somebody insists on naming these poor remains "causality" it is hopeless to convince him, so be it.
It is the standard notion of causality that every scientist acknowledges. And guess what? None of the horror scenarios that you portrayed actually occured. Science is doing fine and progress is made every day.

I have no problem considering Popper. Popper tell's me that a theory which accepts Reichenbachs principle of common cause has a much greater predictive power, because it predicts zero correlation for everything which is not causally connected in the theory.
The common cause for the correlations is the preparation of the state, which is causally connected to the event of observation. QM is actually in full agreement with your beloved principle of common cause.
 
  • #46
rubi said:
It is the standard notion of causality that every scientist acknowledges. And guess what? None of the horror scenarios that you portrayed actually occured. Science is doing fine and progress is made every day.
A horror scenario would appear only if one would take the rejection of Reichenbach's principle seriously and apply it to science in general. This is nothing we should be afraid of. So it simply prevents progress in the explanation of the violations of Bell's inequality - thus, progress toward a more fundamental theory beyond quantum theory.

If such a theory will not be found, because of such rejections, this is not very problematic. It will probably be found some hundred years later anyway. Until this happens, there is enough room yet where a lot of progress can and will be made, in particular by applying Reichenbach's principle. So, no, I do not portray any horror scenario, because I'm sure that scientists will be inconsistent in the rejection of Reichenbach's principle.

And, no, what every scientist acknowledges is only that causality contains also those poor remains. But I doubt that even a large minority of scientists would accept that Reichenbach's principle of common cause could be simply rejected, and that this would not be important for them, because their notion of causality anyway does not contain Reichenbach's principle.

rubi said:
Anyway, we don't need QFT on CST to prove the existence of a manifestly Lorentz covariant quantum theory. There are lots of trivial examples. Just consult Reed & Simon if you're looking for rigorous proofs.
Trivial examples, yes - free particle theories without interactions, as far as I know, and some very special low-dimensional examples. AFAIK, Haag's theorem is yet relevant, not?

rubi said:
The common cause for the correlations is the preparation of the state, which is causally connected to the event of observation. QM is actually in full agreement with your beloved principle of common cause.

Decide what you want to claim:
1.) The principle of common cause holds in QFT.
2.) The relativistic causal structure holds in QFT.
3.) The Bell inequalities are violated in QFT.

Given that the principle of common cause, together with the relativistic causal structure, gives the Bell inequalities, believing all three seems problematic. See for example
E.G. Cavalcanti, R. Lal -- On modifications of Reichenbach’s principle of common cause in light of Bell's theorem, J. Phys. A: Math. Theor. 47, 424018 (2014), arxiv:1311.6852v1 for this.
 
  • #47
rubi said:
The common cause for the correlations is the preparation of the state, which is causally connected to the event of observation.
?
 
  • #48
rubi said:
Not. The Schrödinger formalism is perfectly equivalent to the Heisenberg formalism. You can rewrite any Lorentz covariant theory into a form that doesn't look Lorentz covariant on first sight. Even Maxwell's equations are usually presented in a form the hides the Lorentz covariance and "gives time a preferred role". That doesn't change the fact that they are Lorentz invariant, as can be seen by rewriting them in tensor notation and these formulations are equivalent. It is exactly the same thing for the Schrödinger and Heisenberg picture and it's absolutely trivial to prove the equivalence and it is done in every textbook.
Sorry, but I think you mingle the equivalence of the two formalisms regarding observable predictions with manifest covariance. Manifest covariance means that all parts, even the unobservable parts of the mathematical apparatus, have covariance. A non-covariant formalism may be equivalent to a manifestly covariant one - that means, the predictions about observables will be the same. But this does not make above formalisms manifestly covariant.

The equivalence is indeed quite trivial (if we ignore all the subtleties of field theory) if we fix a time coordinate. But in the Schrödinger formalism this time coordinate plays a very different role than the space coordinates, and nothing in this formalism is manifestly covariant.

I can understand that if you have field operators Phi(x,t) defined for all points of spacetime, then you can define a meaningful way the Poincare group acts on these operators. I can also understand that if you consider complete solutions phi(x,t), say, for a free particle, that an action of the Poincare group on these solutions may be defined.

But if I define a state Psi(Q,t), where Q denotes the configuration of a field, thus, a whole function phi(x), I do not see a simple manifest way to define a nontrivial Lorentz transformation for it.
 
  • #49
zonde said:
I quoted these post from other thread. I don't want to distract discussion in other thread so I'm starting a new one about statements in these posts.

Basically the question is if we can violate Bell inequalities by two separated but correlated systems that can be as non-classical as we like (as long as we can speak about paired "clicks in detectors") i.e. if we give up counter factual definiteness (CFD) but keep locality.
Bhobba and Haelfix are making bold claim that this can be done. But this is just handwaving. So I would like to ask to demonstrate this based on model. Say how using correlated qubits at two spacelike separated places can lead to violation of Bell inequalities in paired detector "clicks"?

Here is an example http://www.ijqf.org/archives/2402. Also, note that it is a realist theory without CFD.
 
  • #50
Ilja said:
Trivial examples, yes - free particle theories without interactions, as far as I know, and some very special low-dimensional examples. AFAIK, Haag's theorem is yet relevant, not?
So you finally acknowledge the fact that there exist perfectly relativistically covariant quantum theories, contrary to your inital claim? (Free QED is already enough to correctly predict the Bell tests by the way.)
Haags theorem is not relevant to the existence of interacting quantum field theories. It just states that they can't be unitarily equivalent to free theories, which is neither necessary nor expected. It is strongly believed that interacting 4d QFT's exist (otherwise the Clay institute wouldn't have put a million dollar bounty on it). It's just that it is mathematically non-trivial and if you look at the details of the interacting phi^4_3 theory, you will see why.

Decide what you want to claim:
1.) The principle of common cause holds in QFT.
2.) The relativistic causal structure holds in QFT.
3.) The Bell inequalities are violated in QFT.

Given that the principle of common cause, together with the relativistic causal structure, gives the Bell inequalities, believing all three seems problematic. See for example
E.G. Cavalcanti, R. Lal -- On modifications of Reichenbach’s principle of common cause in light of Bell's theorem, J. Phys. A: Math. Theor. 47, 424018 (2014), arxiv:1311.6852v1 for this.
The causal relationship I'm talking about is that whenever we prepare the system in a specific entangled state, we will see the correlations and whenever we prepare it in a different state, we don't see the correlations (or see different correlations). Therefore, we can say that the cause for the appearance of the correlations is our preparation of the state. So quantum theory explains the correlations, even if you don't like it, and this is all a scientist needs. If this doesn't satisfy Reichenbachs principle, then Reichenbachs principle is just not a relevant principle, because it is way too strict. And the fact that the only way to save it seems to be to introduce an ether and come up with essentially a conspiracy theory is really more than enough evidence for its rejection.

Derek Potter said:
?
See above.

Ilja said:
Sorry, but I think you mingle the equivalence of the two formalisms regarding observable predictions with manifest covariance. Manifest covariance means that all parts, even the unobservable parts of the mathematical apparatus, have covariance. A non-covariant formalism may be equivalent to a manifestly covariant one - that means, the predictions about observables will be the same. But this does not make above formalisms manifestly covariant.

The equivalence is indeed quite trivial (if we ignore all the subtleties of field theory) if we fix a time coordinate. But in the Schrödinger formalism this time coordinate plays a very different role than the space coordinates, and nothing in this formalism is manifestly covariant.

I can understand that if you have field operators Phi(x,t) defined for all points of spacetime, then you can define a meaningful way the Poincare group acts on these operators. I can also understand that if you consider complete solutions phi(x,t), say, for a free particle, that an action of the Poincare group on these solutions may be defined.

But if I define a state Psi(Q,t), where Q denotes the configuration of a field, thus, a whole function phi(x), I do not see a simple manifest way to define a nontrivial Lorentz transformation for it.
The Lorentz covariance is exactly as manifest as it is in Maxwell's equations. In the Heisenberg picture, you have a non time-dependent state ##\left|\Psi\right>## and operators ##\phi(x,t)## and you get the Schrödinger picture by defining ##\left|\Psi(t)\right> = U(t) \left|\Psi\right>## and ##\phi(x) = U(t)^\dagger \phi(x,t) U(t)##. The state will satisfy the Schrödinger equation defined by the generator of ##U(t)##, as can be easily checked by applying a time-derivative. The time coordinate plays exactly the same role in both pictures. All the expectation values are the same. This is not even specific to quantum theory. You can also formulate classical relativistic theories in an initial-value formulation with a preferred time-coordinate. Even GR has such a formulation (the ADM formalism). There is nothing wrong about rewriting equations in an equivalent way. And even if it were (which it isn't), then free QED in the Heisenberg picture would still be a perfectly manifestly Lorentz covariant quantum theory, which you claim doesn't exist.
 
  • #51
rubi said:
The measurement problem is only a problem to a physicist, who is convinced that there must be some theory of everything that also includes himself. I would argue that this physicist has no basis for his conviction.

Yes, only to a physicist who believes that there is some theory that also includes him or at least his measurement apparatus. One can certainly take your view, as Bohr and Heisenberg did. But as I mentioned, many others including Landau and LIfshitz, Dirac, Weinberg, Bell and Tsirelson did not.

rubi said:
There is certainly always new physics to be discovered, but I see no reason to believe that this new physics must be a classical description, so I don't agree that the violation of Bell's inequality implies that nature must be non-local. I also think that the measurement problem and the violation of Bell's inequality are not necessarily related.

Yes, the next theory beyond quantum theory may also have a measurement problem. However, it the usual sense of the word, "nature" refers to a theory without a measurement problem, and classical theories like general relativity do not have a measurement problem. So Bell's theorem says that if we use such a theory, then it is nonlocal. The measurement problem and Bell's inequality violation are related, because one way of solving the measurement problem is to introduce hidden variables, eg. Bohmian Mechanics. Bell's theorem says that such a theory that reproduces quantum mechanics will be nonlocal.

rubi said:
I don't see how pushing the measurement to the end implies Alice and Bob measure simultaneously. What I'm saying is that textbook derivation of the violation of Bell's inequality with conventional quantum mechanics never references the collapse. All probabilities are calculated with the pre-collapsed state.

By definition, pushing the measurement to the end means Alice and Bob measure simultaneously - is there another option?
 
  • #52
rubi said:
So you finally acknowledge the fact that there exist perfectly relativistically covariant quantum theories, contrary to your inital claim? (Free QED is already enough to correctly predict the Bell tests by the way.)

It is conventional to say it either way that free QED is or is not manifestly relativistically covariant. Wave function collapse means that the wave function evolution is neither covariant nor invariant. However it doesn't matter, since the predictions are relativistically invariant.
 
  • #53
Derek Potter said:
The end is not when Alice and Bob have completed their measurements but when they have shared their measurements with Charles (or each other). This final collation of results is made at time-like separation. In which case it does not matter if Alice measures ahead of Bob. There is no preferred frame, the only criterion is that measurement (collapse) must be postponed until the 4 states have been able to interfere. The fact that Alice and Bob enter Schrodinger Cat states is unfortunate but the conceptual problem for realists was anticipated with Wigner's Friend, here played by Charles.

Yes, that's a slightly more general version of what I said. In either case, there is no violation of the Bell inequalities at spacelike separation, so no implication of nonlocality via the Bell inequalities.
 
  • #54
rubi said:
It is well known that QM doesn't satisfy Bell's locality criterion ("Einstein causality"). That doesn't mean it is not causal. The cause for the correlations is of course that the quantum system has been prepared in a state that results in those correlations. If you prepare the system in a different state, you will not see the same correlations. This is a perfect cause and effect relationship. Bell's locality criterion is just too narrow and doesn't capture the meaning of the word causality adequately. So please don't force your personal definition of causality on everybody else.

Ilja's definition is the conventional definition throughout science. I think many would agree that maybe there is some other definition that makes what you say correct, but so far there are none widely agreed upon. For example, there is brief commentary by Cavalcanti and Lal on proposals like yours (considering the entangled state to be the cause), but these are not yet widely accepted. (At any rate, if the entangled state is the cause, the formalism is manifestly not relativistically invariant).

http://arxiv.org/abs/1311.6852 (p11): "Another way of dropping FP while keeping PCC would be to point out that correlations do not need to be explained in terms of a factorisability condition, but that the quantum state of the joint system in its causal past can itself be considered as the common cause of the correlations. An objection to this point of view, however, is that the precise correlations cannot be determined without knowledge of the measurements to be performed (the inputs x and y in Fig. 1), and these may be determined by factors not in the common past of the correlated events. A similar criticism may be made of the L-S approach. However, an advantage of the latter is that it does give an analogue of the factorisation condition (rather than simply dropping it), and thus could allow for a generalisation of Reichenbach’s Principle of Common Cause in understanding the implication of causal structure for probabilistic correlations, and be of potential application in areas such as causal discovery algorithms."
 
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #55
rubi said:
So you finally acknowledge the fact that there exist perfectly relativistically covariant quantum theories, contrary to your inital claim? (Free QED is already enough to correctly predict the Bell tests by the way.)
What I question is your "perfectly". And I continue to question it, because all the conceptual issues with the measurement problem and so on are simply ignored.

rubi said:
Haags theorem is not relevant to the existence of interacting quantum field theories. It just states that they can't be unitarily equivalent to free theories, which is neither necessary nor expected. It is strongly believed that interacting 4d QFT's exist (otherwise the Clay institute wouldn't have put a million dollar bounty on it).
As if this would matter. I think this only shows that they don't exist - there are enough clever guys who would have found one if it exists given such a price.

Anyway, it would be useless - gravity is at best an effective field theory, and field theory in combination with gravity will not fare better. But effective field theories may have a Lorentz symmetry in their large distance limit, but are conceptually not Lorentz-covariant.
rubi said:
The causal relationship I'm talking about is that whenever we prepare the system in a specific entangled state, we will see the correlations and whenever we prepare it in a different state, we don't see the correlations (or see different correlations).
Yes, fine, but this is not all what Reichenbach's principle is about. The point is that the correlation should be explained by the common cause. In a quite precise sense of probability theory, P(A and B|cc) = P(A|cc) P(B|cc).
rubi said:
Therefore, we can say that the cause for the appearance of the correlations is our preparation of the state. So quantum theory explains the correlations, even if you don't like it, and this is all a scientist needs.
For those who don't like mathematics and formulas, this may be sufficient as an "explanation". Scientists have usually higher requirements for this. The tobacco industry would be, again, very happy if such a verbal description would be all what scientists need to explain correlations.
rubi said:
And the fact that the only way to save it seems to be to introduce an ether and come up with essentially a conspiracy theory is really more than enough evidence for its rejection.
LOL. A big problem - the Lorentz ether interpretation coming back. And, no, the Lorentz ether does not need any conspiracy, this is an old fairy tale for schoolboys. The Poincare group is the symmetry group of a wave equation, and if everything follows the same wave equation, you obtain it automatically without any conspiracy.
rubi said:
The Lorentz covariance is exactly as manifest as it is in Maxwell's equations. In the Heisenberg picture, you have a non time-dependent state ##\left|\Psi\right>## and operators ##\phi(x,t)## and you get the Schrödinger picture by defining ##\left|\Psi(t)\right> = U(t) \left|\Psi\right>## and ##\phi(x) = U(t)^\dagger \phi(x,t) U(t)##. The state will satisfy the Schrödinger equation defined by the generator of ##U(t)##, as can be easily checked by applying a time-derivative. The time coordinate plays exactly the same role in both pictures. All the expectation values are the same. This is not even specific to quantum theory. You can also formulate classical relativistic theories in an initial-value formulation with a preferred time-coordinate. Even GR has such a formulation (the ADM formalism). There is nothing wrong about rewriting equations in an equivalent way. And even if it were (which it isn't), then free QED in the Heisenberg picture would still be a perfectly manifestly Lorentz covariant quantum theory, which you claim doesn't exist.
I repeat, I have a little bit sharper criteria than you for perfection of a theory. I have not seen yet any consistent Lorentz-covariant description of the measurement process. At least none which would be comparable in clarity with the description of the measurement process in de Broglie-Bohm theory, which is clearly non-covariant.

Given that it has also a free QED variant, from its start in Bohm's article, one can compare them with your Lorentz-covariant form. I think that the latter is far from perfect, except in the quite trivial variant of perfectness which simply removes all imperfect things from the consideration.
 
  • #56
Ilja said:
As if this would matter. I think this only shows that they don't exist - there are enough clever guys who would have found one if it exists given such a price.

Haag's theorem doesn't prevent relativistic QFTs from existing, since these have already been constructed in 1+1D and 2+1D.

Ilja said:
I repeat, I have a little bit sharper criteria than you for perfection of a theory. I have not seen yet any consistent Lorentz-covariant description of the measurement process. At least none which would be comparable in clarity with the description of the measurement process in de Broglie-Bohm theory, which is clearly non-covariant.

But Bell's theorem doesn't rule them out - ie. is it possible for nonlocal Lorentz covariant hidden variables to exist? Maybe http://arxiv.org/abs/1111.1425?
 
  • #57
atyy said:
But Bell's theorem doesn't rule them out - ie. is it possible for nonlocal Lorentz covariant hidden variables to exist? Maybe http://arxiv.org/abs/1111.1425?
I think if one relies on causality (requiring Reichenbach's principle and no causal loops) covariant theories are ruled out.

BI excludes common cause, so what remains is or A->B or B->A in arbitrary small environments of A, B. Not above, because no causal loops. Then A->B defines a classical causality connected with a preferred foliation.
 
  • #58
atyy said:
Yes, only to a physicist who believes that there is some theory that also includes him or at least his measurement apparatus. One can certainly take your view, as Bohr and Heisenberg did. But as I mentioned, many others including Landau and LIfshitz, Dirac, Weinberg, Bell and Tsirelson did not.
I agree that one can also take the other point of view and I accept that people do so. I just wanted to explain that one doesn't need to and quantum theory can be a very satisfactory theory if one doesn't.

Yes, the next theory beyond quantum theory may also have a measurement problem. However, it the usual sense of the word, "nature" refers to a theory without a measurement problem, and classical theories like general relativity do not have a measurement problem. So Bell's theorem says that if we use such a theory, then it is nonlocal. The measurement problem and Bell's inequality violation are related, because one way of solving the measurement problem is to introduce hidden variables, eg. Bohmian Mechanics. Bell's theorem says that such a theory that reproduces quantum mechanics will be nonlocal.
Well, I would say that "nature" refers to nature and a theory is just a representation of some ideas about nature in the language of mathematics. We can't read off what nature is by looking at a mathematical theory.

By definition, pushing the measurement to the end means Alice and Bob measure simultaneously - is there another option?
Pushing the measurement to the end means that you are describing the situation from the outside, i.e. you have a third observer. But as a matter of fact, Alice and Bob perform measurements at spacelike separated intervals and the results are consistent with the statistics that is predicted by the pre-collapsed state.

atyy said:
Ilja's definition is the conventional definition throughout science. I think many would agree that maybe there is some other definition that makes what you say correct, but so far there are none widely agreed upon. For example, there is brief commentary by Cavalcanti and Lal on proposals like yours (considering the entangled state to be the cause), but these are not yet widely accepted. (At any rate, if the entangled state is the cause, the formalism is manifestly not relativistically invariant).
I believe that the majority of quantum physicists would agree that Reichenbachs criterion is too strong for application in quantum theory.

Ilja said:
What I question is your "perfectly". And I continue to question it, because all the conceptual issues with the measurement problem and so on are simply ignored.
Perfectly means that the theory is invariant under the Poincare group. This is the definition of a Lorentz covariant theory.

As if this would matter. I think this only shows that they don't exist - there are enough clever guys who would have found one if it exists given such a price.

Anyway, it would be useless - gravity is at best an effective field theory, and field theory in combination with gravity will not fare better. But effective field theories may have a Lorentz symmetry in their large distance limit, but are conceptually not Lorentz-covariant
So the remaining 5 unsolved millenium problems also unsolvable, since nobody has solved them yet? This is a hilarious claim. Anyway, I can only tell you that you will not find a single person working in the area of rigorous QFT who seriously believes that 4d Yang-Mills doesn't exist. It's seen about as unlikely as assuming that P=NP will turn out right. But of course you are invited to submit your refutation of the remaining millenium problems and collect the 5 million dollars. We can talk about it again, when I read about it in the news.

Loop quantum gravity provides a rigorous potential theory of quantum gravity coupled to all known standard model matter. It would really be helpful if you didn't randomly mention all these subjects that you clearly don't really understand as if it would be in favour of your argument.

Yes, fine, but this is not all what Reichenbach's principle is about. The point is that the correlation should be explained by the common cause. In a quite precise sense of probability theory, P(A and B|cc) = P(A|cc) P(B|cc).
Well, Reichenbachs principle needs to be rejected then if it forces us to give up a perfectly satisfactory theory. It's not like Reichenbachs principle is something that nature must necessarily obey. Nature can behave as she may and we have to accept that. Religous believes like yours have no place in science.

For those who don't like mathematics and formulas, this may be sufficient as an "explanation". Scientists have usually higher requirements for this. The tobacco industry would be, again, very happy if such a verbal description would be all what scientists need to explain correlations.
Real scientists will give up a theory if it can't be rescued in a reasonable way. And Reichenbachs principle is such a theory.

LOL. A big problem - the Lorentz ether interpretation coming back. And, no, the Lorentz ether does not need any conspiracy, this is an old fairy tale for schoolboys. The Poincare group is the symmetry group of a wave equation, and if everything follows the same wave equation, you obtain it automatically without any conspiracy
Bohmian mechanics definitely needs a conspiracy to explain why the Lorentz violation cannot be observed (arXiv:1208.4119). Even the paper you quoted earlier comes to this conclusion. And introducing an ether with all its consequences when there is really no need for it is just not reasonable.

I repeat, I have a little bit sharper criteria than you for perfection of a theory. I have not seen yet any consistent Lorentz-covariant description of the measurement process. At least none which would be comparable in clarity with the description of the measurement process in de Broglie-Bohm theory, which is clearly non-covariant.

Given that it has also a free QED variant, from its start in Bohm's article, one can compare them with your Lorentz-covariant form. I think that the latter is far from perfect, except in the quite trivial variant of perfectness which simply removes all imperfect things from the consideration.
Every phenomenon has an equivalent discription in every inertial frame and they are connected by Lorentz transformations. This is what Lorentz covariance means. If you don't agree that this is the definition of Lorentz covariance, then I'm wasting my time here.
 
  • #59
To me, the details of QFT or QM are not so relevant to the issue of locality/causality/etc. as the bare facts of EPR correlations. To me, that's the core question, is whether Bell's-inequality-violating correlations are somehow nonlocal (in the sense of SR).

The perfect correlations in EPR seem to imply a strong connection between distant experiments. As a correlation, it's nonlocal. But it doesn't violate SR's prohibition against FTL propagation of information. But those two facts together are strange. Why [itex]doesn't[/itex] it?

The distinction is between something I would call "factorizability" and "signal locality". Factorizability is just the claim that the evolution of distant subsystems proceeds independently. Roughly speaking, what happens at Alice's location should depend only on conditions local to Alice, and what happens at Bob's location should depend only on conditions local to Bob. That is, facts about Bob's situation shouldn't tell us anything about Alice's future results, unless those results are somehow determined by conditions local to Alice. EPR violates the principle of factorizability. But this violation is not visible in the equations of QFT or QM. Those equations are perfectly factorable, it is only when you interpret the amplitudes as probability distributions for measurements that non-factorizability comes in.

Signal locality is weaker than factorizability, but in a strange way (or it seems strange to me). There is a failure of factorizability if knowing facts about Bob's situation reveals something about Alice's future results (in a way that local knowledge of Alice's situation doesn't). But Bob's situation has two sort-of independent components:

  1. Choices made by Bob.
  2. Choices made by "nature"--that is, random events.
Signal locality basically amounts to factorizability for Bob's choices. If all you know is what Bob's choices are, that'll tell you nothing about what's going to happen to Alice that couldn't be predicted using Alice's local conditions. So Bob's choices can't influence Alice's results.

This distinction between factorizability and signal locality causes philosophical problems for me, no matter what interpretation of "locality" you're using. For some people, signal locality is all that's important, so they're perfectly happy with saying QM is local (or is not nonlocal, to make a fine distinction). But I have problems with that. What is special about "choices made by agents"? Why should physics particular care about those sources of unpredictability?

On the other hand, saying that the violation of Bell's inequality implies that nature is nonlocal is unsatisfying for other reasons. If interactions are nonlocal at the fundamental level (as they are in the Bohmian interpretation of QM), then why can't it be used for FTL signalling? I certainly understand the proof that it can't be, but it seems very ugly and suspicious to have a fundamental fact about the universe (such as the rest frame relative to which these nonlocal interactions are instantaneous) be inherently undetectable.
 
  • Like
Likes zonde
  • #60
But there does seem to be a sense in which Bob's setting and outcome in a particular trial *do* influence Alice's result in EPR-Bell. For example, consider the Mermin device (Mermin, N.D.: Bringing home the atomic world: Quantum mysteries for anybody. American Journal of Physics 49, 940-943 (1981)) where Bob chooses setting 1 and finds an outcome of R (say). As Mermin shows, it can't be the case that conditions local to Alice already existed for outcomes in each of the three possible settings (no CFD), so knowing Bob's setting and outcome tells you something that couldn't have been know otherwise before Alice actually chooses her setting and obtains her result.
 
  • #61
stevendaryl said:
This distinction between factorizability and signal locality causes philosophical problems for me, no matter what interpretation of "locality" you're using. For some people, signal locality is all that's important, so they're perfectly happy with saying QM is local (or is not nonlocal, to make a fine distinction). But I have problems with that. What is special about "choices made by agents"? Why should physics particular care about those sources of unpredictability?
I agree that it would be much less mysterious if nature just did behave classically. But unfortunately she doesn't and at some point we just have to accept it and adopt the most reasonable explanation. After taking all possibilities into consideration, I've personally come to the conclusion that we have to accept the fact that there is a peculiar thing like quantum probability theory that we just don't quite understand yet. The reason I think so is that it applies universally to every phsical theory. If quantum probabilities weren't a thing, then why can we apply quantum theory to large effective systems without even knowing the actual details of the interactions? If there were a fundamental theory, then we wouldn't expect that simplifying it would still pertain its structure as a quantum theory. But as a matter of fact, the quantum framework works nicely at all levels of complexity. I can imagine that one day we might even successfully apply it to models of economics. And economics clearly isn't a theory of physics.

(Of course, everyone is allowed to have their own opinion. I just don't accept it if people like Ilja force their personal prejudices upon others, especially if there is no evidence in favour of them.)
 
  • #62
rubi said:
I agree that one can also take the other point of view and I accept that people do so. I just wanted to explain that one doesn't need to and quantum theory can be a very satisfactory theory if one doesn't.

I think one should be clear that those who take the "other point of view" are not claiming that quantum theory is not a very satisfactory theory. In the same spirit that one can take QED to be a very satisfactory theory because of the Wilsonian effective theory point of view, one can also say that very satisfactory theories can themselves indicate their incompleteness and point towards theoretical opportunities.

rubi said:
Well, I would say that "nature" refers to nature and a theory is just a representation of some ideas about nature in the language of mathematics. We can't read off what nature is by looking at a mathematical theory.

I think your language is unusual. If you would like to just say quantum theory is not a theory about what nature is, but what we can say about nature, ie. predict the probabilities of outcomes, then that would be fine. But going on to say that quantum theory explains the observations is controversial. Usually, in the operational view the wave function is not taken to be real, and just a tool. If the wave function is taken to be an explanation, then it is taken to be real, and collapse is real, and relativistic invariance is manifestly violated.

rubi said:
Pushing the measurement to the end means that you are describing the situation from the outside, i.e. you have a third observer. But as a matter of fact, Alice and Bob perform measurements at spacelike separated intervals and the results are consistent with the statistics that is predicted by the pre-collapsed state.

No, it means that Bob includes Alice as part of his classical apparatus and Alice includes Bob as part of her classical apparatus. So the measurement that is performed is the simultaneous measurement by Alice and Bob. However, using this method to avoid collapse will create a preferred frame, since it takes the frame in which Alice and Bob measure simultaneously. To avoid the preferred frame, one cannot accept the reality of measurements at spacelike intervals.

rubi said:
II believe that the majority of quantum physicists would agree that Reichenbachs criterion is too strong for application in quantum theory.

Yes, perhaps the precise statement of Reichenbach's principle might not be agreed on by everyone. However, Ilja is much closer to consensus than you are - there is no widely accepted notion of cause in which quantum theory explains the correlations.

rubi said:
IBohmian mechanics definitely needs a conspiracy to explain why the Lorentz violation cannot be observed (arXiv:1208.4119). Even the paper you quoted earlier comes to this conclusion. And introducing an ether with all its consequences when there is really no need for it is just not reasonable.

The paper makes separate comments about Valentini's version of Bohmian Mechanics.
 
  • #63
rubi said:
(Of course, everyone is allowed to have their own opinion. I just don't accept it if people like Ilja force their personal prejudices upon others, especially if there is no evidence in favour of them.)

I'm pretty sure Ilja's view is the common one, or at least the one that is closer to correct. The problem with your view is that you go beyond the view that the role of quantum theory is only to predict the correlations, which is the operational view of Bohr and Heisenberg, and all who believe there is a measurement problem also agree the operational view is very satisfactory. But to go beyond that and say that quantum theory "explains" or is about "causes" and can maintain relativistic invariance is very controversial.
 
  • #64
atyy said:
Yes, that's a slightly more general version of what I said. In either case, there is no violation of the Bell inequalities at spacelike separation, so no implication of nonlocality via the Bell inequalities.
I disagree. Alice and Bob are spacelike separated. The violation occurs. They are both spacelike separated from Charles when the photons are detected. The violation occurs.

I suspect that what you mean is that the observation (to fix the results) has to wait until further down Charles' world-line, where he can receive their results. But whilst that may save locality, it forces us to assume that Charles' classical observation of Alice and Bob's classical data is what collapses their wavefunction(s). So Alice and Bob's lives are put on hold until their data intersect. Good job photons are pretty nifty so it's all over in a few microseconds, but I wonder how this would work with cold electrons where Alice and Bob remain in Schrodinger Cat states for half an hour? Perhaps we should ask them what it was like... oh I forgot, their memories get wiped at the same time as the forbidden data.
 
  • #65
Derek Potter said:
I disagree. Alice and Bob are spacelike separated. The violation occurs. They are both spacelike separated from Charles when the photons are detected. The violation occurs.

To be clear, here I always use Copenhagen, so measurement is something which produces a classical result.

If Alice and Bob measure at spacelike separation, one can choose a frame in which their measurements are not simultaneous. In which case, one will have collapse.

To get rid of collapse, one has to use the frame in which Alice and Bob measure simultaneously. However, that means that there is a preferred frame.

To get rid of collapse and to get rid of the preferred frame, one has to say that there is no reality to Alice's measurement at spacelike separation.

Derek Potter said:
I suspect that what you mean is that the observation (to fix the results) has to wait until further down Charles' world-line, where he can receive their results. But whilst that may save locality, it forces us to assume that Charles' classical observation of Alice and Bob's classical data is what collapses their wavefunction(s). So Alice and Bob's lives are put on hold until their data intersect. Good job photons are pretty nifty so it's all over in a few microseconds, but I wonder how this would work with cold electrons where Alice and Bob remain in Schrodinger Cat states for half an hour? Perhaps we should ask them what it was like... oh I forgot, their memories get wiped at the same time as the forbidden data.

Almost except that Alice and Bob have no classical data. They don't really exist, and are just ghostly things in the wave function which is not real. When Charles measures them, he observes he classical result that Alice and Bob report that they violated the Bell inequality at spacelike separation. However, only the report received by Charles is real Alice and Bob and their experiments are not real.
 
Last edited:
  • #66
atyy said:
Almost except that Alice and Bob have no classical data. They don't really exist, and are just ghostly things in the wave function which is not real. When Charles measures them, he observes he classical result that Alice and Bob report that they violated the Bell inequality at spacelike separation. However, only the report received by Charles is real Alice and Bob and their experiments are not real.
That will be news to Alice and Bob. And I thought the LSD-dropping hippies were wierd.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #67
atyy said:
To be clear, here I always use Copenhagen, so measurement is something which produces a classical result.
If Alice and Bob measure at spacelike separation, one can choose a frame in which their measurements are not simultaneous. In which case, one will have collapse.
To get rid of collapse, one has to use the frame in which Alice and Bob measure simultaneously. However, that means that there is a preferred frame.
I don't think simultaneity solves anything except making it much harder to think about. The wavefunction collapses under two observations: in stages if Alice and Bob stagger their observations, in one step if they are simultaneous.
atyy said:
To get rid of collapse and to get rid of the preferred frame, one has to say that there is no reality to Alice's measurement at spacelike separation.
No *classical* reality. But we know this anyway even without a preferred frame. And we are not trying to get rid of collapse because we are in love with MWI, we need to postpose it otherwise Bob's detector is being affected by an event at Alice which, in some frames, hasn't even happened yet.
 
  • #68
atyy said:
I think your language is unusual. If you would like to just say quantum theory is not a theory about what nature is, but what we can say about nature, ie. predict the probabilities of outcomes, then that would be fine. But going on to say that quantum theory explains the observations is controversial. Usually, in the operational view the wave function is not taken to be real, and just a tool. If the wave function is taken to be an explanation, then it is taken to be real, and collapse is real, and relativistic invariance is manifestly violated.
I pretty much completely agree with the operational view. I might just have a different standard for what I consider a possible explanation. For me, a theory that describes every aspect of a phenomenon accurately, is already a possible explanation. You seem to additionally require an explanation to be philosophically pleasing. I also prefer philosophically pleasing models, but for me it is not a necessary condition for an explanation.

No, it means that Bob includes Alice as part of his classical apparatus and Alice includes Bob as part of her classical apparatus. So the measurement that is performed is the simultaneous measurement by Alice and Bob. However, using this method to avoid collapse will create a preferred frame, since it takes the frame in which Alice and Bob measure simultaneously. To avoid the preferred frame, one cannot accept the reality of measurements at spacelike intervals.
I'm pretty sure that if you are not going to collapse the state anyway, i.e. you are just using it as a tool that encodes available information, you can just apply a Lorentz transform to it to get an equivalent description in any other inertial frame. The unitarity of the transformation ensures that all predictions must be equivalent.
But my point really wasn't about a no-collapse interpretation. What I'm saying is that even in plain Copenhagen with collapse, the probabilities that lead to a Bell inequality violation are calculated using only the pre-collapsed state, so it is really the entanglement and not the collapse, which causes the violation.

Yes, perhaps the precise statement of Reichenbach's principle might not be agreed on by everyone. However, Ilja is much closer to consensus than you are - there is no widely accepted notion of cause in which quantum theory explains the correlations.
This is not what i meant to imply. I agree that it is uncommon to regard the preparation procedure as cause of the correlations. What I'm saying is that I'm fairly sure that the majority of physicists don't know Reichenbach's principle and will reject it as soon as you tell them that it implies Lorentz violation, the exception being the rather negligible group of Bohmians.

The paper makes separate comments about Valentini's version of Bohmian Mechanics.
Ok, but Valentini's version seems to be a version that actually dares to make experimental predictions that contradict conventional quantum mechanics. I happily encourage this kind of research, since it may actually lead to an expansion of our understanding.

atyy said:
I'm pretty sure Ilja's view is the common one, or at least the one that is closer to correct. The problem with your view is that you go beyond the view that the role of quantum theory is only to predict the correlations, which is the operational view of Bohr and Heisenberg, and all who believe there is a measurement problem also agree the operational view is very satisfactory. But to go beyond that and say that quantum theory "explains" or is about "causes" and can maintain relativistic invariance is very controversial.
I explained above what my standard for an admissible explanation is. I'm not forcing anyone to adopt the same standard. However, I don't think that it is controversial to say that relativistic quantum theories maintain Lorentz invariance.

atyy said:
Almost except that Alice and Bob have no classical data. They don't really exist, and are just ghostly things in the wave function which is not real.
I don't think that one is forced to adopt such a point of view. After all, the wave function may just be a container for information about statistics of repeated identically prepared experiments.
 
  • #69
rubi said:
Well, Reichenbachs principle needs to be rejected then if it forces us to give up a perfectly satisfactory theory. It's not like Reichenbachs principle is something that nature must necessarily obey. Nature can behave as she may and we have to accept that.
Real scientists will give up a theory if it can't be rescued in a reasonable way. And Reichenbachs principle is such a theory.
No. It corresponds nicely with de Broglie-Bohm theory. That you don't like a theory does not make it unreasonable.
rubi said:
Bohmian mechanics definitely needs a conspiracy to explain why the Lorentz violation cannot be observed (arXiv:1208.4119).
Big problem. Ok, I do not say that a fine tuning problem is not a problem at all - it is an interesting problem worth to be considered, because the solution of this problem will probably give some additional insight, for example some symmetry.

But the problem in this paper does not have much to do with Lorentz symmetry - it is a general problem of a superposition: If one measures one part, the reduction of the wave function gives information about what has been measured as well as the result of the measurement - but this information remains invisible in the probabilities. Thus, the same problem appears also in non-relativistic QM if one applies the same technique.

And, it appears, dBB solves it - it is the "conspiracy" defined by quantum equilibrium, which creates a 1:1 correspondence between the probability distribution of the configuration and the wave function.

PS: Finishing reading the paper, I have seen that this has already been recognized in the paper itself, in the part where Valentini's variant is considered.
rubi said:
And introducing an ether with all its consequences when there is really no need for it is just not reasonable.
What would be these so horrible consequences that it is preferable to give up such essential fundamental concepts like Reichenbach's principle?

rubi said:
Religous believes like yours have no place in science.
...
It would really be helpful if you didn't randomly mention all these subjects that you clearly don't really understand as if it would be in favour of your argument.
...
If you don't agree that this is the definition of Lorentz covariance, then I'm wasting my time here.
One should indeed think about if it is only a waste of time to have discussions with people who behave in such a way, so I have deleted the answers to the remaining points, leaving only those where I'm interested enough to find out if you have some arguments or not.
 
Last edited:
  • #70
rubi said:
It is well known that QM doesn't satisfy Bell's locality criterion ("Einstein causality"). That doesn't mean it is not causal. The cause for the correlations is of course that the quantum system has been prepared in a state that results in those correlations. If you prepare the system in a different state, you will not see the same correlations. This is a perfect cause and effect relationship.

I don't think that that's the full story, for the same reason that Einstein, Rosen and Podolsky said. Consider an EPR-type twin-pair experiment where Alice and Bob decide ahead of time to choose the same orientation for their spin (or polarization) measurements. Furthermore, suppose that Alice performs her measurement slightly before Bob performs his. Then in the time between those measurements, Alice knows for certain what result Bob will get. So, if Alice were to describe the state of affairs near Bob's detector, then she would have to describe it by a density matrix, or probability distribution, or wave function, or whatever that gave 100% chance for certain outcomes and 0% chance for other outcomes. That's a different state than she would have used a moment before. So the state that she ascribes to Bob's detector/particle changes discontinuously.

That doesn't mean anything nonlocal is going on, if the state that Alice ascribes to Bob is subjective. But it isn't just subjective. Whether anyone else besides Alice knows it, it is certain what result Bob will get (unless you want to get many-worlds about it).
 

Similar threads

Replies
71
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
16
Views
2K
Replies
25
Views
2K
Replies
93
Views
5K
Replies
49
Views
3K
Replies
4
Views
2K
Replies
70
Views
7K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
999
Replies
66
Views
5K
Back
Top