Probability Postulate in Relativistic QM?

In summary: EPR pairs (two particles in a state with the same Spin).This is a really long-winded answer to your question. Basically, the Born rule is just a way of calculating the probability of a state given the state and the measurement done on it.
  • #1
LarryS
Gold Member
345
33
In non-relativistic QM, the probability postulate works very well in position and momentum space. But, I have read that in relativistic QM (Dirac or QFT), the probability postulate in position space does not work because the corresponding probability density function is not Lorentz covariant. But, what about probability in momentum space in relativistic QM? Is a probability interpretation also not possible there - is it also not Lorentz covariant?

Thanks in advance.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
In non-relativistic QM, the probability postulate is the Born rule, which is given in various forms of increasing generality in http://arxiv.org/abs/1110.6815. Even in non-relativistic QM, it does not refer specifically to position or momentum. The Born rule also holds in relativistic quantum theory, except that the observables and the states are different. The general rules from non-relativistic QM do carry over to relativistic quantum theory, and yield Lorentz invariant probabilities, eg. http://arxiv.org/abs/1007.3977.
 
  • #3
atyy:

Ok, but I can find no references to "Born rule" or "probability" in either of my QFT books or in other online sources for QFT. What are the "different" "observables" and "states" that you refer to that have a probabilistic interpretation in relativistic QM?
 
  • #4
referframe said:
atyy:

Ok, but I can find no references to "Born rule" or "probability" in either of my QFT books or in other online sources for QFT. What are the "different" "observables" and "states" that you refer to that have a probabilistic interpretation in relativistic QM?

In some cases the field itself is an observable in QFT. Roughly, in QM (including QFT) the order in which non-commuting observables are measured matters. If A and B do not commute, measuring A before B changes the distribution of B, compared to when B is measured before A. Thus, in relativistic QFT, if measurements are taken at spacelike separation, the observables must commute, otherwise there might be faster than light transmission of classical information. The requirement in relativistic QFT that spacelike observables commute is found in eg. http://www.damtp.cam.ac.uk/user/tong/qft.html (Eq. 2.86). That the field itself is an observable is not so obvious in QFT books, because there is a long chain from correlators of fields to the LSZ formula to scattering cross sections etc to get a match to how experiments are done.

The Born rule is rarely stated in QFT books because all the postulates of QM are assumed, but one can find the Born rule stated eg. in the QFT texts of Weinberg https://www.amazon.com/dp/0521670535/?tag=pfamazon01-20 (Eq 2.1.7) and Haag https://www.amazon.com/dp/3540610499/?tag=pfamazon01-20 (Eq I.3.1).
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #5
Scratching my head about this one.

I thought it was implicit in the propagator, <x|x'> which is used extensively in QFT, |<x|x'>|^2 gives the probability of being at position x then later being at position x'.

Or am I missing something?

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #7
atyy said:
He's probably referring to difficulties with a position operator in relativistic quantum theory, eg. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/5427/.

Agreed that is a big issue. There is also the issue the state resides in a Fock space.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #8
First of all one should mention that the very fundamental principles of quantum theory are the same in non-relativistic and relativistic theory. The Born rule is a the heart of the application of the Hilbert-space formalism to describe real-world experiments. Any good QFT book (my favorites are the three volumes by Weinberg, Quantum Theory of Fields) mentions it in the beginning (perhaps not under the name Born's rule).

In short it's as follows: A (pure) state can be represented by a ray in Hilbert space, which itself can be represented equivalently by the statistical operator ##\hat{\rho}=|\psi \rangle \langle \psi|##, where ##|\psi \rangle## is any normalized vector in the ray.

An observable (like position, momentum, angular momentum, etc.) is represented by a self-adjoint operator on the Hilbert space. Possible values are the eigenvalues of the operators. Suppose you measure an observable ##A## (represented by the self-adjoint operator ##\hat{A}##) on a system prepared in the state represented by ##\hat{\rho}##. Let ##a## by an eigenvalue of ##\hat{A}## and ##|a,\beta \rangle## a complete set of orthonormal eigenvectors to the eigenvalue ##a##. Then Born's rule states that
$$P_{\psi}(a)=\sum_{\beta} \langle a,\beta|\hat \rho a,\beta \rangle.$$

This formalism shows you that to define the probabilities correctly first of all you need an observable. The observable algebra built by the operators representing the observables is determined from a modern form of the correspondence principle: You look for representations of the symmetry group of the physical system. The most important symmetry underlying all physics is the symmetry structure of space-time. In the case of non-relativistic quantum theory it's the Galilei group for special-relativistic theory it's the Poincare group.

As it turns out for massive particles (the only case making sense in non-relativistic QT as this also comes out of the symmetry analysis based on the Galilei group) of any spin (also spin comes out of the symmetry analysis in a quite natural way) there can be defined a position observable in both non-relatistic and relativistic theory.

In relativistic QT there's also the possibility of massless quanta like the photon. It turns out that you cannot define a position observable for massless particles with spin ##s \geq 1##.

It's also pretty intuitive, why the localization of a relativistic particles makes problems: To localize a particle well you must confine it somehow to a small volume in space, which e.g., can be done with various kinds of traps. Now according to the Heisenberg-Robertson uncertainty relation, ##\Delta x \Delta p \geq \hbar/2## (which is valid in both non-relativistic and relativistic theory, provided there exists a position observable in the strict sense). This implies the better you confine the particle to a small area, i.e., the smaller the standard deviation of position, ##\Delta x##, becomes, the broader the spread ##\Delta p## in momentum space. This means with quite some probability the particles can have large momentum. Hitting the "wall" (in reality some kind of potential well provided by the trap) with high momentum however means that according to the relativistic QFT there's always some probability to create new particles destroying the original particle you wanted to localize. For massless particles it's very easy to create very soft ones from hitting a potential well with a harder one (like for photons, you need charged particles to confine it and hitting with a photon a charged particle it will wiggle around and emit more radiation, i.e., photons), because there's no energy threshold for creation of a massless particle.
 
  • #9
referframe said:
the probability postulate in position space does not work because the corresponding probability density function is not Lorentz covariant.
It is true that it is not Lorentz covariant, but it does not necessarily need to be a problem. According to the operational view of QM, the aim of QM is not to give the probability that the particle is at certain position. Instead, its aim is to give the probability that the particle will be found at certain position. In the latter case, the probability only has a contextual meaning, i.e. it only makes sense when there is a measuring apparatus that will measure an observable. Each apparatus defines a distinguished Lorentz frame, the one in which the apparatus is at rest. Therefore, in a purely operational QM, physical observables do not need to be Lorentz covariant.

By the way, something similar occurs even in classical (non-quantum) relativity. Due to Lorentz contraction, the length of a rod transforms from one Lorentz frame to another in a non-covariant way. The length of a rod is neither a Lorentz scalar, nor a Lorentz vector or tensor. Yet, there is an experimental procedure which (in principle) can measure Lorentz contraction.

There is also an example in general relativity. The gravitational force, being related to Christoffel connections, is also not a tensor and hence not a covariant object. Yet, the gravitational force can certainly be measured, probably more easily than any other "observable" in general relativity.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and bhobba

Related to Probability Postulate in Relativistic QM?

What is the Probability Postulate in Relativistic QM?

The Probability Postulate in Relativistic QM states that the probability of a system being in a certain state is equal to the absolute value squared of the wave function for that state. In other words, the probability of finding the system in a particular state is proportional to the amplitude of the wave function for that state.

What does the Probability Postulate tell us about the nature of quantum systems?

The Probability Postulate reveals that quantum systems are inherently probabilistic in nature. This means that it is impossible to know with certainty the exact state of a system at any given time, and instead, we can only predict the probability of finding the system in a certain state.

How does the Probability Postulate relate to the Uncertainty Principle?

The Probability Postulate is closely related to the Uncertainty Principle, which states that it is impossible to know both the position and momentum of a particle with absolute certainty. This is because the wave function, which is used to calculate the probability of finding a particle in a certain state, contains both position and momentum information.

Can the Probability Postulate be used to predict the behavior of quantum systems?

Yes, the Probability Postulate is a fundamental principle of quantum mechanics and is used to make predictions about the behavior of quantum systems. By calculating the probabilities of different states, we can make predictions about the outcomes of experiments and observations on quantum systems.

How does the Probability Postulate differ from classical mechanics?

In classical mechanics, the state of a system can be known with absolute certainty at any given time. In contrast, the Probability Postulate in Relativistic QM tells us that the state of a quantum system is inherently uncertain and can only be described in terms of probabilities. This is one of the key differences between classical mechanics and quantum mechanics.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
40
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
3
Replies
87
Views
5K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
7
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
19
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
34
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
3
Replies
87
Views
7K
Replies
9
Views
2K
Replies
36
Views
3K
Replies
21
Views
1K
Back
Top