Negation of nested quantifiers

  • MHB
  • Thread starter agapito
  • Start date
In summary, the expression 1 + 2 is equivalent to the expression 1 + (1 + 1), after replacing 2 with (1 + 1).
  • #1
agapito
49
0
Consider the expression:

~ Ex Ay Ez P(x,y,z), where

~ is negation symbol, E existential quantifier, A universal quantifier.

We are asked to prove formally that, after instantiation of x to a, we obtain:

~ Ay Ez P(a,y,z)

How might we go about this? I appreciate all help,

agapito
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Consider the following problem: "Suppose we have an expression 1 + 2. Prove that after replacing 2 with (1 + 1), we get 1 + (1 + 1)". It's hard to argue against it: this is just a question of replacing a substring with another substring. So it may not be exactly clear what we are asked to prove.

Note, however, that after replacing we don't get an arbitrary new expression; the numerical value of the new expression is equal to that of the old one: 1 + 2 = 1 + (1 + 1). One could consider a similar problem: "Suppose we have an expression 1 + 2. Prove that after replacing 2 with (1 + 3), we get 1 + (1 + 3)". This is equally true, but it is somewhat strange that we replaced 2 with 1 + 3 = 4, so the value of the new expression is not equal to the value of the old one. Unlike the first problem, replacing 2 with 1 + 3 seems unjustified.

In the same way, logic is about rules manipulating strings of symbols. We define certain rules because they have some meaning: for example, they preserve the truth value of logical formulas. (Formally the choice of rules is justified by the so-called soundness theorem.) But once the rules are chosen, the only question is, "Can we get from this string to that string by following these rules?". You could always replace some substring by any other substring (e.g., instantiate $x$ with $a$), and nobody will doubt that you did that. But the question is whether this is done in accordance with the rules, or whether the new formula has some expected relationship with the old one.

In your problem it seems that what one needs to prove is that $\neg\forall y\exists z\,P(a,y,z)$ logically follows from (or is in some other sense implied by) $\neg\exists x\forall y\exists z\,P(x,y,z)$. This is indeed so, but to approach it you need to clarify the problem statement. Is it about logical (semantic) consequence or about syntactic consequence (derivability)? In the second case you need to provide the logical calculus that is used in your course or book: axioms and rules of inference. But the idea is that $\neg\exists x\ldots$ is equivalent to $\forall x\neg\ldots$, and one can instantiate a universally quantified variable and get a consequence of the formula.
 
  • #3
Thank you very much for your explanation. I'm actually looking for a proof of the material equivalence

¬∃x∀y∃z P(x,y,z) <---> ∀x ¬∀y∃z P(x,y,z)

in terms of syntactic consequence. My text, Copi's Symbolic Logic shows it as a rule. Does it make sense to inquire if there is some basic principle supporting the rule?

Thanks again for helping me out with this,

agapito
 
  • #4
agapito said:
I'm actually looking for a proof of the material equivalence

¬∃x∀y∃z P(x,y,z) <---> ∀x ¬∀y∃z P(x,y,z)

in terms of syntactic consequence. My text, Copi's Symbolic Logic shows it as a rule. Does it make sense to inquire if there is some basic principle supporting the rule?
This is a special case of
\[
\neg\exists x\,A\longleftrightarrow\forall x\,\neg A.\qquad(*)
\]
That this formula is always true is clear: an object satisfying $A$ does not exists iff all objects don't satisfy $A$. As for a syntactic proof, one needs to specify axioms and rules of inference. There is no way around it. There are dozens of logical calculi, just like dozens of programming language, and asking for a formal proof of a formula without specifying a calculus makes as much sense as asking to write an actual program without specifying a language. Wikipedia, for example, lists around 20 calculi only of a certain style and only for propositional logic.

But the equivalence (*) is indeed quite fundamental, and a lot can be said about it.
 
  • #5
OK, many thanks for your help.
 

Related to Negation of nested quantifiers

What is the definition of negation of nested quantifiers?

The negation of nested quantifiers is a logical operation that involves negating the entire statement of a nested quantifier. This means that the negation applies to all the individual quantifiers within the statement, rather than just one of them.

What is an example of negation of nested quantifiers?

One example of negation of nested quantifiers is the statement "For every x, there exists a y such that x + y > 10". The negation of this statement would be "There exists an x for which there does not exist a y such that x + y > 10".

What is the relationship between negation of nested quantifiers and De Morgan's laws?

Negation of nested quantifiers follows a similar principle to De Morgan's laws, which state that the negation of a conjunction or disjunction is equivalent to the disjunction or conjunction of the negated statements, respectively. In the case of nested quantifiers, the negation applies to the entire statement, rather than just part of it.

Why is negation of nested quantifiers important in mathematics and logic?

Negation of nested quantifiers is important in mathematics and logic because it allows for the creation of complex statements that can be easily negated. It also helps to clarify the meaning of a statement and can lead to more precise and accurate reasoning and proofs.

How does negation of nested quantifiers affect the truth value of a statement?

Negation of nested quantifiers can change the truth value of a statement. For example, if the original statement is true, its negation will be false, and vice versa. However, there are some cases where the original statement and its negation may both be false, such as when the statement contains contradictory quantifiers.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
841
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
991
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
8
Views
875
  • General Math
Replies
3
Views
1K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
2
Views
333
Back
Top