Entanglement, why are the spins decided on observation?

In summary: In quantum Mechanics, we often talk about "quantum entanglement". This is a bit of a mouthful, but essentially, it means that two particles are in a state where their properties are correlated (even if they are separated by vast distances). For instance, if I generate two photons, and I send one of them to you, then the other photon will have a certain polarization. Even if I send you a completely random photon (not related to the first one in any way), it will still have the polarization of the photon that I sent you.
  • #1
Superposed_Cat
388
5
Hi all, I'm not really seeing why entanglement is such a big deal, if total spin was 0 and the particles it creates can only have spin 1/2 and spin +1/2 then if one is down the other must be up, so they have spins designated at birth so to speak, what makes us think they don't have spin till measured? Any help apreciated, thanks. I'd prefer the proof to involve maths if there is one.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Google for "Bell's Theorem", and pay particular attention to the site maintained by our own DrChinese.
 
  • Like
Likes Superposed_Cat, bhobba and DrChinese
  • #3
Superposed_Cat said:
Hi all, I'm not really seeing why entanglement is such a big deal, if total spin was 0 and the particles it creates can only have spin 1/2 and spin +1/2 then if one is down the other must be up, so they have spins designated at birth so to speak, what makes us think they don't have spin till measured? Any help apreciated, thanks. I'd prefer the proof to involve maths if there is one.

If a pair of particles had their spins determined at birth, then knowing all pieces of information about the histories of both particles would explain any correlation we see,

Because of this, we can get mathematical consequences of such statements.
These mathematical consequences are known as Bell inequalities.

Remarkably, scientists have done very careful experiments which show that real measurement outcomes do not obey Bell inequalities.

Because of this, we can conclude that their spins are not somehow already determined at birth.
What this ultimately means, is still being resolved to this day.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba, Superposed_Cat and Johan0001
  • #4
Thank you all
 
  • #5
I'll wade into this one a bit.

It's my understanding that this proof is not exactly about violations of Bell's inequalities. They are violated either way. However, if we can argue that the polarization was established at the creation of the EPR pairs, then local causality (with nothing traveling faster than c) can be used as an explanation of the observed correlations in polarization. This is one of the "loopholes" often discussed when dealing with these issues.

The mathematics is the superpositioned |ψ〉 vector and it's associated basis states defined by how it might be measured. (We can think of the rotation angle of a polarization filter that we might use for measurement as defining our basis states.)

The question is whether or not there is superposition at the point of measurement (or whether the polarization angle was determined at the point the EPR pair was created).

I'll outline an experimental configuration that I believe can sort it out, but I'll leave it to others to actually work out the proof.

Let's assume we have an EPR pair creator, and also a station A and station B, both at some distance (in opposite directions) from our EPR pair creator. Now, let's assume that both station A and station B have equipment to measure the polarization angle of their respective EPR entangled photons. This is a simple polarization filter with a back-plate to see if the photon got through. Let's further assume that station B has the ability to rotate their polarization filter at incredibly fast speeds (so fast that they can rotate it and also measure their photon faster than light could travel from station A to station B). I believe that this setup, along with the correlation that emerges when measuring several EPR pairs is enough to show that polarization is not determined at EPR pair creation (and that superposition is maintained until measurement).

I look forward to comments from others.

Regards,
Elroy

p.s. All of my thinking was in terms of linearly polarized photons (polarized at random angles). Elliptical and circular polarizations can be brought in as well, but they just confuse the issue rather than making it more clear.
 
  • #7
Oh gosh, I know Nugatory. I'm hopefully just allowing for the opportunity for me and others to think through the consequences of these experiments.
 
  • #8
After some contemplation, I've decided to ask a related question in this thread. I hope it's not viewed as hijacking the thread. Here's the question:

What is superposition (of, let's say, the polarization of a photon)?​

In a certain sense, this is exactly the same question that Superposed_Cat asked. But let's think few a couple of relevant points.

* We often "measure" a photon (with measurement defined as sending it through a polarizer and then seeing if it got through). And, after measurement, we often say that it has "collapsed" into a certain state. However, any state, from an alternative perspective can be viewed as continued superposition. For instance, if we send a photon through a vertical polarizer (and it gets through), then, if we send it through a polarizer at 45°, it will appear superposed (with half getting through and half not getting through). Therefore, we can't say that all the photons (that got through) "collapsed" into the exact same state.

* To reiterate the above, any "known" state (basis state) of a photon can be viewed differently and then appear superposed.

* We can also bring elliptical and circular polarization into this. For instance, let's say our polarization filter has the ability to not only filter linearly, but it has the ability to polarize elliptically and circularly as well. We often "imagine" linear polarizers as a "slit" in a screen. And we rotate this slit to measure linear polarizations at different angles. However, we might imagine that this "slit" can be "stretched open" making an ellipse. When it's "fully stretched open", it makes a circle. If we stretch it open even more, it just closes on the orthogonal axis (Y vs X, or X vs Y, with Z being the direction of photon progression). So, with an ellipse, we still have a major axis.

When we talk of elliptical or circular polarization, we can also talk about whether the photon wave is rotating clockwise or counter-clockwise (depending on how the phase is offset in the Z direction). This brings up an interesting point. It can be argued that, when a photon is sent through a vertical linear polarizer (and it gets through), that it is in a state of circular superposition. We don't know if it's undulating down first and then up, or if it's undulating up first and then down. We would have to send it through a circular polarizer to determine that, which would "collapse" (destroy, superpose) it's linear polarization. Therefore, without even changing our angle, we can view linear polarization as a continuing superposition. In a similar vein, we can argue that circular polarization is a superposition of vertical and horizontal linear polarizations.

---

The concept of a Bloch sphere attempts to visually represent all possible polarization states, with the X,Z plane representing all linear polarizations (including their superpositions), whereas any non-zero value on the Y axis (regardless of X or Z values) represents elliptical and/or circular polarizations. (Values of Y=1 or Y=-1 would be circular, with values of Y closer to zero indicating elliptical polarization.)

Even with this visual concept of the Bloch sphere, we still have the unit Bloch vector pointing in some specific direction (defined by the polar coordinates theta and phi, where theta is 2 times the linear polarization and phi is the phase offset representing elliptical and circular polarization). To say again, we still have the unit Bloch vector. Therefore, from some specific perspective, the photon is NOT in superposition, whereas, from all other perspectives it IS in superposition. Sure, we move the Bloch vector every time we take a measurement, but this argument still holds.

Should we abandon the use of the word "collapsed" and, instead, use the words "reoriented as per measurement"? When we "peek into" the Bloch sphere at some point on the surface, if the Bloch vector isn't pointing straight at us, we then know that it's pointing directly away from us.

Does superposition truly make sense in terms of a single photon? Might we do better to say "random polarization among a group of photons"? And then, this goes back to Superposed_Cat's question. If we can argue that a single photon is NOT superposed from "some" perspective (even if that perspective is unknown), then why can't we say that that unknown perspective was determined at the emission of the photon from our EPR pair creator (and not at the time of measurement), thereby reclaiming Einstein's local causality?

Just some things I'm thinking about.
Again, I look forward to comments, even if they show flaws in my thinking.
 
Last edited:
  • #9
I'm kind of confused on this issue myself. But the importance of Bell's theorem seems to me to be the following. (Do please shout me down if I'm wrong.)

Given quantum mechanics you can show an inequality. This inequality will be obeyed if the world is quantum mechanical. To get the world to be both causal and deterministic (i.e., not quantum mechanical) this inequality must be violated.

So, in order to build a theory that retains both causality (only events inside the backward light cone can influence an event) and determinism (the outcome of an experiment is determined uniquely by the inputs) you must violate Bell's inequality.

However, you can keep causality if you give up determinism. And this is the usual situation in quantum mechanics. The "spooky action at a distance" only arises if you insist on viewing every event as determined exactly. If events are only probabilistic then the seeming violation of causality entirely goes away.

Example: Suppose you had two arms of an experiment that measured spin "here" and "there" from a central source. You might think that spin up here determines spin down there, and that this amounts to sending a signal faster than light. You might think that you could sit on one side of the system and have the other be arbitrarily far away. Then you could agree that spin up here meant "1" and there spin down meant "1". You might think you could use this to send a signal. If the locations were light years apart (as one such experiment has been done using signals from pulsars that went through gravity lenses and split in two) you might think you could send a signal many light years in zero time.

But you cannot determine in advance that you will see spin up here. So you cannot use this to send a signal. The event is not deterministic, so the causal problem goes away.
 
  • #10
It would be possible to set up an experiment so that it's observer-dependent which one of the entangled particles is measured first. If the information about the spins is not contained in the particles when they are created, nor the first measured particle can tell the other what spin it should have even FTL (because it's observer-dependent, not absolute, which is first), I cannot imagine how it's possible that the particles behave the way it seems to be. Should we think that entanglement is something that happens "outside of spacetime" i.e. the spacetime concepts do not exatly apply?
 
  • #11
DEvans, hopefully I would never shout you down. :)

However, as I understand it, you have the interpretation of Bell's inequality exactly backwards.

DEvens said:
Given quantum mechanics you can show an inequality. This inequality will be obeyed if the world is quantum mechanical. To get the world to be both causal and deterministic (i.e., not quantum mechanical) this inequality must be violated.

There is a good thread where we've been discussing these very issues:

https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/bells-inequality.791592/

Please take a look at this thread. Several of us have done a fair job of precisely outlining this point.

Regards,
Elroy
 
  • #12
Elroy said:
* We often "measure" a photon (with measurement defined as sending it through a polarizer and then seeing if it got through). And, after measurement, we often say that it has "collapsed" into a certain state. However, any state, from an alternative perspective can be viewed as continued superposition. For instance, if we send a photon through a vertical polarizer (and it gets through), then, if we send it through a polarizer at 45°, it will appear superposed (with half getting through and half not getting through). Therefore, we can't say that all the photons (that got through) "collapsed" into the exact same state.

* To reiterate the above, any "known" state (basis state) of a photon can be viewed differently and then appear superposed.

You're right, that for a single photon, the superposition of two polarization states is just a third polarization state. So there is no unique notion of the photon being in a superposition.

However, what the EPR experiment is about is entanglement. That occurs when you have a pair of particles that are in a correlated superposition of states. With one type of entangled photons, you produce two photons that have the same polarization, but which polarization that is, is nondetermined. You can represent this as

[itex]\sqrt{2} (|H\rangle |H\rangle + |V\rangle |V\rangle)[/itex]

where [itex]|H\rangle |H\rangle[/itex] means that both photons are horizontally polarized, and [itex]V\rangle |V\rangle[/itex] means that both photons are vertically polarized. It's not just that the photons are in a superposition of horizontally and vertically polarized states, but they are in correlated states. It's a superposition of (1) both are vertically polarized, and (2) both are horizontally polarized. That is not equivalent to any other nonentangled state.
 
  • #13
Yes, I think I "get" the concept (and the mathematics) of, say, putting a qubit through a Hadamard gate and then putting it and another qubit through a CNOT gate, which is effectively what you mathematically outlined. I further understand, if Alice and Bob measure in the same way, that a perfect ("spooky") correlation will emerge.

Also, just so you know, I will be working hard to clear this up in my own head, in the interim.

However, here's what I'm still confused about. One of the three "loopholes" (as I understand it, there are three) in the EPR paradox is that the photon pairs were correlated at the point of emission/creation, therefore obviating any need for faster than speed of light explanations. Maybe our EPR pair creator device is incapable of creating anything other than "randomly polarized" pairs, but still pairs that are both polarized in the same (or exactly opposite) ways upon creation.

Stated differently, you've claimed that the EPR pairs are in the following state:

|ψ⟩ = √2 |H⟩|H⟩ + √2 |V⟩|V⟩

And what I'm claiming is that maybe they were in either
|ψ⟩ = 1 |H⟩|H⟩ + 0 |V⟩|V⟩
or
|ψ⟩ = 0 |H⟩|H⟩ + 1 |V⟩|V⟩
upon initial creation, although we don't know which until we measure them. Furthermore, even though which state is unknown, it's not "unknowable" (i.e., for a specific EPR pair, it's not probabilistic).

I think I may have outlined the answer to my own question in post #5 above, but I'll admit that I've yet to get complete clarity on this point. Also, it's pretty much the point of the thread.

Regards,
Elroy
 
  • #14
Elroy said:
Yes, I think I "get" the concept (and the mathematics) of, say, putting a qubit through a Hadamard gate and then putting it and another qubit through a CNOT gate, which is effectively what you mathematically outlined. I further understand, if Alice and Bob measure in the same way, that a perfect ("spooky") correlation will emerge.

Also, just so you know, I will be working hard to clear this up in my own head, in the interim.

However, here's what I'm still confused about. One of the three "loopholes" (as I understand it, there are three) in the EPR paradox is that the photon pairs were correlated at the point of emission/creation, therefore obviating any need for faster than speed of light explanations. Maybe our EPR pair creator device is incapable of creating anything other than "randomly polarized" pairs, but still pairs that are both polarized in the same (or exactly opposite) ways upon creation.

Stated differently, you've claimed that the EPR pairs are in the following state:

|ψ⟩ = √2 |H⟩|H⟩ + √2 |V⟩|V⟩

And what I'm claiming is that maybe they were in either
|ψ⟩ = 1 |H⟩|H⟩ + 0 |V⟩|V⟩
or
|ψ⟩ = 0 |H⟩|H⟩ + 1 |V⟩|V⟩
upon initial creation, although we don't know which until we measure them. Furthermore, even though which state is unknown, it's not "unknowable" (i.e., for a specific EPR pair, it's not probabilistic).

That's what Bell's Theorem proves is NOT the case. Your theory would explain the result if someone measured the spin in the [itex]H[/itex] direction or the [itex]V[/itex] direction, but it wouldn't explain what happens if someone uses a filter that is, say, oriented at [itex]45^o[/itex] relative to the horizontal. If the photons were really in the state [itex]|V\rangle |V\rangle[/itex], and the two experimenters both set their filters at [itex]45^o[/itex] relative to horizontal, then the results would be:

  1. 25% of the time, both photons would pass the filters.
  2. 50% of the time, only one of the two photons would pass.
  3. 25% of the time, neither would pass.
That's the prediction of your model, but with the entangled state, the results are:
  1. 50% of the time, both photons pass.
  2. 50% of the time, neither pass.
 

Related to Entanglement, why are the spins decided on observation?

1. What is entanglement and how does it work?

Entanglement is a quantum phenomenon in which two or more particles become connected, or "entangled," in such a way that the state of one particle is dependent on the state of the other. This means that even if the particles are separated by large distances, they will still exhibit correlated behavior. The exact mechanism behind entanglement is still not fully understood, but it is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics.

2. How are the spins of entangled particles decided on observation?

The spins of entangled particles are not determined until they are observed or measured. This is known as the "measurement problem" in quantum mechanics. When a measurement is made on one of the entangled particles, the state of the other particle is instantly determined, regardless of the distance between them. This is known as "quantum entanglement collapse."

3. Can entanglement be used for communication?

No, entanglement cannot be used for communication. While entangled particles may exhibit correlated behavior, there is no way to control or manipulate the state of one particle to send a message to the other. This is due to the fact that the state of the particles is only determined upon observation, and therefore cannot be used to transmit information.

4. What are the potential applications of entanglement?

Entanglement has potential applications in quantum computing, quantum cryptography, and quantum teleportation. By utilizing the correlated behavior of entangled particles, scientists are exploring ways to develop more powerful and secure computing systems, communication networks, and teleportation technology.

5. Can entanglement be observed in everyday objects?

No, entanglement is a quantum phenomenon that only occurs at the subatomic level. While we may not be able to observe entanglement directly in everyday objects, its effects can be seen in certain materials and behaviors, such as superconductivity and superfluidity. These phenomena are believed to be a result of entanglement between particles.

Similar threads

Replies
12
Views
975
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
14
Views
826
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
41
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
8
Views
743
Replies
8
Views
1K
Replies
35
Views
2K
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
7
Views
702
Back
Top