Does the wave function really collapse into a state?

In summary, the double slit experiment is a thought experiment used to illustrate the wave-particle duality. The wave function for the photon is a superposition of two orthogonal states, one for each slit passage. It is claimed to collapse into one of these two states when the photon hits the screen beyond, and then continue in this one state. But when the photon hits the screen, it is totally absorbed and ceases to exist. How can one then claim that its wave function collapses into a state?
  • #1
Erland
Science Advisor
769
148
Take the famous double slit (thought) experiment. The wave function for the photon is a superposition of two orthogonal states, one for each slit passage. But it is claimed to collapse into one of these two states when the photon hits the screen beyond, and then continue in this one state.
But when the photon hits the screen, it is totally absorbed and ceases to exist. How can one then claim that its wave function collapses into a state? It does not exist anymore, in any state at all, or...?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Erland said:
The wave function for the photon is a superposition of two orthogonal states, one for each slit passage. But it is claimed to collapse into one of these two states when the photon hits the screen beyond, and then continue in this one state.
Where does that come from? The idea of the double-slit is the impossibility of that.
Erland said:
But when the photon hits the screen, it is totally absorbed and ceases to exist. How can one then claim that its wave function collapses into a state? It does not exist anymore, in any state at all
You can say the wavefunction collapsed to "how the world looks like if there was a photon in this specific state and then got absorbed".

Note that there are interpretations of quantum mechanics without collapses.
 
  • #3
Erland said:
But when the photon hits the screen, it is totally absorbed and ceases to exist. How can one then claim that its wave function collapses into a state? It does not exist anymore, in any state at all, or...?

There are two ways to deal with the collapse postulate here.

(1) Recall that in the Copenhagen interpretation the wave function is not real, and is only a tool to calculate the probabilities of events. The collapse postulate only applies when successive measurements are made. When the photon is absorbed, there is (commonly) no successive measurement, and the wave function is not needed beyond the first measurement, so collapse is irrelevant.

(2) The collapse postulate as projection is too restricted, and must be generalized to allow for collapse into other states. In this more general framework, for photons one uses a second quantized description, in which the state of zero photons is a state. See http://arxiv.org/abs/1110.6815 (p13, comment R2). For the generalization of projective measurements, see http://arxiv.org/abs/0706.3526 (Eq 2 & 3).
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #4
Just to add to atyy's posting: If photons, i.e., the electromagnetic field, are involved you must use a "second-quatization description". There is no such thing as a wave function of a single- or many-photon system, because there is not even a position operator for photons in the usual sense. So the only consistent description of photons is Quantum Electrodynamics (QED), i.e., "second quantization" of classical electrodynamics.

The name "second quantization" is, however, a misnomer since there's only one quantization. QFT is only the most general form to formulate quantum theory. It includes the possibility of creation and destruction of quanta, i.e., situations, where you don't have a conservation law that fixes the number of quanta. The latter is, strictly speaking, only possible in non-relativistic quantum theory. In relativistic quantum theory the creation and destruction of quanta (particles or photons) are very common as soon as the necessary energy is involved in collisions of particles and/or fields.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy and Nugatory
  • #5
Erland said:
Take the famous double slit (thought) experiment.

You may be interested in seeing a correct analysis of the experiment:
http://cds.cern.ch/record/1024152/files/0703126.pdf

Its a bit different from the usual textbook treatment because it uses QM to explain it, rather than use it motivate QM.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #6
I have removed an interesting but basically off-topic digression from this thread.
 
  • #7
Q. Does the wave function really collapse into a state?
A. In terms of de Broglie's Double Solution theory the answer is no as the wavefunction is a statistical, non-physical, mathematical construct.
 
  • Like
Likes zoki85
  • #8
bhobba said:
You may be interested in seeing a correct analysis of the experiment:
http://cds.cern.ch/record/1024152/files/0703126.pdf

Its a bit different from the usual textbook treatment because it uses QM to explain it, rather than use it motivate QM.

Thanks
Bill
The text in the above link is heavily misleading. Position or momentum "eigen vectors" not representing states. They are generalized functions and live in the dual of the domain of the position and momentum operators (see you favorite Book by Ballentine). It is highly misleading to analyze any quantum situation by starting with wrong statements like this! The correct treatment must use wave packets.

This is also true for the standard treatment of scattering processes. You cannot simply use plane waves as asymptotic states to derive the formula for the cross section. The correct treatment with wave packets can be found in, e.g.,

Peskin, Schroeder, Introduction to Quantum Field Theory.
 
  • #9
vanhees71 said:
The text in the above link is heavily misleading. Position or momentum "eigen vectors" not representing states.

It has definite issues and a guy wrote a critique of it:
http://arxiv.org/pdf/1009.2408.pdf

Its purpose however is to break down the common misconception the double slit experiment demonstrates wave-particle duality.

I think anyone advanced enough to understand its issues is advanced enough to know what a crock the wave-particle duality is.

Small steps mate, small steps :D:D:D:D:D:D.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #11
Erland said:
But when the photon hits the screen, it is totally absorbed and ceases to exist. How can one then claim that its wave function collapses into a state? It does not exist anymore, in any state at all, or...?
Photon does not longer exist, but the state of the quantum system (a generalized wave function, mathematically described as a wave functional) still exists. This state is a state in a Fock space, in which the number of particles may not be fixed.
 
  • #12
I think the Stern–Gerlach experiment is a better one to shine some light on this issue, especially the triple-SG experiment.

In 3-SG, the middle SG apparatus clearly "does something" to the silver atoms, since it clearly affects what happens at the last SG apparatus. IOW, to me this experiment seems to be an experimental proof that collapse is real.
 
  • #13
nikkkom said:
to me this experiment seems to be an experimental proof that collapse is real.

It's proof that the SG apparatus does something to the silver atoms, but it doesn't follow that that something is necessarily wave function collapse.
 
  • #14
Nugatory said:
It's proof that the SG apparatus does something to the silver atoms, but it doesn't follow that that something is necessarily wave function collapse.

After first SG apparatus atoms fly away in two narrow streams, they have definite spins (up and down) along selected axis (say, x axis).

After second SG apparatus atoms fly away in two narrow streams, they have definite spins (up and down) along a different selected axis (say, y).

Naively classically thinking, I'd expect the atoms in each stream have definite spin components in both x and y axes.

But third apparatus shows that "definitedness" along x-axis was lost. The second apparatus "made spin definite along y" (thus "collapse" sounds like a fitting word) but destroyed "definitedness" along x-axis (thus, this "collapse" thing is real - it has observable consequences).
 
  • #15
nikkkom said:
But third apparatus shows that "definitedness" along x-axis was lost. The second apparatus "made spin definite along y" (thus "collapse" sounds like a fitting word) but destroyed "definitedness" along x-axis (thus, this "collapse" thing is real - it has observable consequences).

You can choose to think of it that way, but there's nothing in the formalism of quantum mechanics that says that you have to - indeed, there's nothing in that formalism that even says that the wave function is real, let alone a real thing that can collapse. With QM, the only thing that you get without ambiguity is statements about the results of measurements.

There are many problems, including just about all that involve a straightforward series of observations on a single article, in which you'll get the right intuition if you think in terms of the wave function being something real and collapsible. Thus, this approach appeared early in the history of quantum mechanics and is still taught today - it's useful. But there are plenty more problems where thinking of the wave function as something real and collapsible will just get in the way.
 
  • #16
nikkkom said:
I think the Stern–Gerlach experiment is a better one to shine some light on this issue, especially the triple-SG experiment.

In 3-SG, the middle SG apparatus clearly "does something" to the silver atoms, since it clearly affects what happens at the last SG apparatus. IOW, to me this experiment seems to be an experimental proof that collapse is real.

If there are no irreversible operations by any Stern-Gerlach apparatus, you should be able to combine all the beams back before the last apparatus and show they are still coherent, which is a prediction different from collapse in which coherence is lost.

I have not actually worked it out for 3SG (so maybe my comments don't hold for 3SG), but you can find a simpler example where the beams are recombined after a single SG in Ballentine's textbook (https://www.amazon.com/dp/9810241054/?tag=pfamazon01-20, section 9.5). I think the single SG example is good enough, since what you seem to be saying is that even a single SG causes collapse. I don't normally recommend Ballentine, because it is such an erroneous book. Anyway, Ballentine actually uses this to say that collapse after a measurement is wrong. Ballentine is wrong, because a (strictly alone) SG apparatus implements a unitary operation. Measurement requires an irreversible macroscopic mark to be made. So while Ballentine is right that there no collapse by an SG apparatus, he is wrong about the lack of collapse after measurement because there is no measurement either.

In order to have measurement in an SG apparatus, the apparatus cannot be strictly alone. At the quantum level, one can put in a measuring ancilla, and trace out the ancilla. A more careful treatment of the SG experiment than Ballentine's erroneous discussion can be found in http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0306072 (see Figure 1, where the SG apparatus is not strictly alone, but includes a detector).

Edit: Also, just in case there is any misunderstanding: the wave function is not necessarily real, and neither is collapse. So no experiment can "prove" collapse, rather the wave function and collapse are just tools to calculate the probabilities of events. Within Copenhagen which is where collapse is usually used, the events are real, but the wave function and collapse are not necessarily real. As long as observations match the predictions, we accept the wave function and collapse as valid tools.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #17
Erland wrote that on the screen the particle was in superposition of two paths and had to choose one of them.
Of course this not correct.
In interferometers nature only offers the choice between the possible recorded ouputs of the device.
So Erland could have written that on the screen detector the particle is in a superposition of orthogonal positions (states or operators)
 
  • #18
Nugatory said:
there's nothing in that formalism that even says that the wave function is real, let alone a real thing that can collapse. With QM, the only thing that you get without ambiguity is statements about the results of measurements.

I am not talking about "reality" of wavefunctions. I'm taking experimentalist view here. I'm saying that experimental fact is that 2nd (y-axis) SG apparatus affects silver atoms' x-axis spin (destroys their polarization in that axis), and it's reality. It's up to theoreticians to explain it, but they can't deny that it happens.
 
  • #19
nikkkom said:
I'm saying that experimental fact is that 2nd (y-axis) SG apparatus affects silver atoms' x-axis spin (destroys their polarization in that axis)

That I won't argue with.

However that's not the claim that you made above that "this experiment seems to be an experimental proof that collapse is real". The undisputed experimental fact is that that silver atoms behave in a particular way in an S-G device. Wave function collapse is one way of explaining this fact, but it's not the only way - and you'll have to unlearn it at some point.
 

Related to Does the wave function really collapse into a state?

1. What is the wave function and why does it collapse into a state?

The wave function is a mathematical description of the probability of a quantum particle being in a certain state. It is based on the principles of quantum mechanics, where particles can exist in multiple states at once. The collapse of the wave function occurs when the particle is observed or measured, and its state is determined.

2. Is the collapse of the wave function a physical process or just a mathematical concept?

This is a debated topic in the field of quantum mechanics. Some scientists believe that the collapse of the wave function is a real physical process, while others argue that it is simply a mathematical concept used to describe the behavior of quantum particles.

3. Can the collapse of the wave function be predicted or controlled?

At this point, it is not possible to predict or control the collapse of the wave function. The exact mechanism of collapse is not fully understood, and it is a probabilistic event. However, there are ongoing research efforts to better understand and potentially manipulate the collapse of the wave function.

4. Does the collapse of the wave function violate the laws of physics?

No, the collapse of the wave function does not violate any known laws of physics. It is a fundamental principle of quantum mechanics and has been observed in numerous experiments. The concept of collapse may seem counterintuitive, but it is crucial for understanding the behavior of quantum particles.

5. What are the implications of the collapse of the wave function in practical applications?

The collapse of the wave function has significant implications in practical applications, particularly in the field of quantum computing. It allows for the manipulation and measurement of quantum states, which is essential for the development of advanced quantum technologies. It also has implications in other fields such as cryptography and quantum communication.

Similar threads

Replies
1
Views
719
Replies
59
Views
4K
Replies
23
Views
2K
Replies
18
Views
2K
Replies
16
Views
1K
Replies
8
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
9
Views
841
Replies
7
Views
1K
Replies
28
Views
4K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Back
Top