Why we need completeness of eigenfuntions for QM to be internally consistent?

  • I
  • Thread starter Happiness
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Qm
In summary, quantum mechanics requires the eigenfunctions of an observable operator to span the entire Hilbert space in order to be internally consistent. This is proven by the spectral theorem, which states that any function in Hilbert space can be expressed as a linear combination of eigenfunctions. If the eigenfunctions do not span the entire space, it results in inconsistencies and violates the principles of probability theory. In addition, there is an existence and uniqueness theorem for a bivariate second-order linear partial differential equation, which is applicable to the Schrodinger equation in quantum mechanics.
  • #1
Happiness
679
30
For quantum mechanics to be internally consistent, the following must be true:
The eigenfunctions of an observable operator are complete: Any function (in Hilbert space) can be expressed as a linear combination of them.

In other words, it is not alright for the solution space (to the Schrodinger equation) to span only a subspace of the Hilbert space. It has to span the entire Hilbert space. But why? What's inconsistent about it?

I find this quite unbelievable, because it's saying any function in Hilbert space is a solution to Schrondinger equation. But when we solve an equation, we don't expect everything to turn out to be a solution.

Reference: Introduction to Quantum Mechanics, 2nd ed., David J. Griffiths, p 102.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Why? Because it is a provable theorem, valid in each Hilbert space. It is called the spectral theorem.

Note that linear combinations of eigenstates are generally not eigenstates again.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and vanhees71
  • #3
Happiness said:
For quantum mechanics to be internally consistent, the following must be true:In other words, it is not alright for the solution space (to the Schrodinger equation) to span only a subspace of the Hilbert space. It has to span the entire Hilbert space. But why? What's inconsistent about it?

I find this quite unbelievable, because it's saying any function in Hilbert space is a solution to Schrondinger equation. But when we solve an equation, we don't expect everything to turn out to be a solution.

Reference: Introduction to Quantum Mechanics, 2nd ed., David J. Griffiths, p 102.
What is important about the Schrodinger equation is the time evolution of states. In principle , any wave function could be a starting point, but how it evolves is really the solution.

This is not that different from the 1D wave equation, where the wave can, in theory, have any shape.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and vanhees71
  • #4
Well, there are some exceptions from the arbitrariness of initial states, the socalled superselection rules, which are closely related to symmetries. E.g., there should be no superpositions of states with half-integer and integer spin in order to have a proper (ray) representation of the rotations as symmetry group of both Galilei and Minkowski spacetime. In non-relatistic QT, there should also be no superpositions of states with different mass.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #5
The time-independent Schroedinger equation is a spectral equation whose solutions, if the self-adjoint Hamiltonian has a pure-point spectrum, span the whole Hilbert space. This is plain, not simple mathematics. If the Hamiltonian is not self-adjoint, there is no guarantee that the whole spectrum has no complex numerical value. We cannot measure 5+4i J, right?
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and vanhees71
  • #6
If the eigenfunctions of some observable operator don't span the whole space, and you have a system in a state given by a wave function in the complement of the span, and you make a measurement of that observable, then what result can you get!?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #7
martinbn said:
If the eigenfunctions of some observable operator don't span the whole space, and you have a system in a state given by a wave function in the complement of the span, and you make a measurement of that observable, then what result can you get!?
You get the eigenvalue of the eigenfunction closest to the wave function. Would this make QM consistent?
 
  • #8
Happiness said:
You get the eigenvalue of the eigenfunction closest to the wave function. Would this make QM consistent?
No, it's wrong. You get any eigenvalue, with a probability decreasing with that distance.
 
  • #9
A. Neumaier said:
No, it's wrong. You get any eigenvalue, with a probability decreasing with that distance.
Ok, that answers @martinbn’s question.
 
  • #10
Happiness said:
Ok, that answers @martinbn’s question.
It wasn't a question, it was an answer. It seemed than the given answers didn't satisfy you, so I tried to give you a more intuitive answer. I'll try again. When you measure an observable the possible results are eigenvalues of the corresponding operator with probabilities given by the Born rule. If the eigenvectors of the operator do not span the whole space, and your system is in a state that is in the orthogonal compliment of that span, when you perform a measurement the probability to obtain any of the eigenvalues will be zero. And after the measurement the state of the system will be reduced to the zero vector. That is absurd, hence the span of the eigenvectors should be the whole space.
 
  • Like
Likes Happiness
  • #11
Indeed, it violates the basics of probability theory: If you have a probability distribution for a well-defined random experiment (and according to quantum mechanics all physics experiments are in a well specified sense random experiments) the probabilities must add up to 1, i.e., when measuring an observable (with an ideal measurement device) you always get a well-defined result, though the measured observable may not have had a determined value before the measurement. That's implied by any probabilistic description of random experiments. If this is not the case it's ill-defined, i.e., you have to find a better description.

That's, by the way, the formal reason, why observables (usually) are described by self-adjoint operators (and Hermitean operators is too weak an assumption). The important point is not so much that the possible measurement outcomes, i.e., the eigenvalues of the operator, are real but that self-adjoint operators have a complete spectral decomposition, i.e., there exists a complete set of orthonormal generalized eigenvectors (including the case of continuous eigenvalues, where you have to generalize the concept of eigenvectors in the sense of the theory of generalized functions, the most elegant formulation being the "rigged Hilbert space").
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #12
PeroK said:
In principle , any wave function could be a starting point, but how it evolves is really the solution.
Is there an existence (and uniqueness) theorem for a bivariate second-order linear partial differential equation?

In other words, does the equation $$a(x,t)\frac{\partial^2}{\partial t^2}y(x,t)+b(x,t)\frac{\partial}{\partial t}y(x,t)+c(x,t)y(x,t)+d(x,t)\frac{\partial^2}{\partial x^2}y(x,t)+e(x,t)\frac{\partial}{\partial x}y(x,t)+f(x,t)\frac{\partial^2}{\partial x\partial t}y(x,t)=g(x,t)$$ always have a (unique) solution ##y(x,t)## for any given ##y(x,0)##, ##\frac{\partial y}{\partial t}(x,0)##, ##\frac{\partial y}{\partial x}(x,0)##, ##a(x,t)##, ##b(x,t)##, ##c(x,t)##, ##d(x,t)##, ##e(x,t)##, ##f(x,t)## and ##g(x,t)##?

(##y(x, t)## is in Hilbert space, just like wave functions are.)
 
Last edited:
  • #13
Happiness said:
Is there an existence (and uniqueness) theorem for a bivariate second-order linear partial differential equation?

In other words, does the equation $$a(x, t)\frac{\partial^2}{\partial t^2}y(x, t)+b(x, t)\frac{\partial}{\partial t}y(x, t)+c(x, t)y(x, t)+d(x, t)\frac{\partial^2}{\partial x^2}y(x, t)+e(x, t)\frac{\partial}{\partial x}y(x, t)+f(x, t)\frac{\partial^2}{\partial x\partial t}y(x, t)=g(x, t)$$ always have a (unique) solution ##y(x, t)## for any given ##y(x, 0), a(x, t), b(x, t), c(x, t), d(x, t), e(x, t), f(x, t)## and ##g(x, t)##?
The question is too vague for an answer. It is second order in ##t## and includes hyperbolic equations, say the wave equation, so you need the initial value for the derivative too. It also includes elliptic equations, say Poison equation, for which the Cauchy problem is ill posed. Also you don't specify what space the given functions belong to. It is like asking does the equations ##x^3-2=0## have a unique solution. In rationals, no, in reals it has on, in complex numbers three.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and dextercioby
  • #14
martinbn said:
The question is too vague for an answer. It is second order in ##t## and includes hyperbolic equations, say the wave equation, so you need the initial value for the derivative too. It also includes elliptic equations, say Poison equation, for which the Cauchy problem is ill posed. Also you don't specify what space the given functions belong to. It is like asking does the equations ##x^3-2=0## have a unique solution. In rationals, no, in reals it has on, in complex numbers three.
##y(x, t)## is in Hilbert space, just like wave functions are.
 

Related to Why we need completeness of eigenfuntions for QM to be internally consistent?

1. Why is completeness of eigenfunctions important in quantum mechanics?

The completeness of eigenfunctions is crucial in quantum mechanics because it ensures that any physical state of a system can be described as a linear combination of the eigenstates of the system. This allows us to accurately predict the behavior of the system and make precise measurements.

2. How does completeness of eigenfunctions relate to the uncertainty principle?

The completeness of eigenfunctions is directly related to the uncertainty principle in quantum mechanics. This is because the uncertainty principle states that the more precisely we know the position of a particle, the less precisely we can know its momentum, and vice versa. Completeness of eigenfunctions allows us to accurately describe the possible states of a particle, which in turn allows us to calculate the probabilities of measuring different values for position and momentum.

3. Can quantum mechanics be internally consistent without completeness of eigenfunctions?

No, quantum mechanics would not be internally consistent without completeness of eigenfunctions. This is because the completeness of eigenfunctions is a fundamental principle in quantum mechanics that allows us to accurately describe and predict the behavior of quantum systems. Without it, the theory would not be able to explain the observed phenomena and make accurate predictions.

4. How does the concept of superposition relate to completeness of eigenfunctions?

The concept of superposition, where a quantum system can exist in multiple states at the same time, is only possible because of the completeness of eigenfunctions. This is because completeness of eigenfunctions allows us to express the state of a system as a linear combination of eigenstates, and superposition is essentially a combination of these states. Without completeness of eigenfunctions, superposition would not be possible.

5. What are the implications if completeness of eigenfunctions is not satisfied in a quantum system?

If completeness of eigenfunctions is not satisfied in a quantum system, it would mean that the system cannot be accurately described using quantum mechanics. This would have significant implications for our understanding of the behavior of particles at the quantum level and would likely lead to inconsistencies and contradictions in our predictions and observations. Therefore, the completeness of eigenfunctions is a crucial aspect of quantum mechanics that must be satisfied for the theory to be internally consistent.

Similar threads

Replies
9
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
6
Views
929
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
69
Views
5K
Replies
6
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
13
Views
1K
Replies
35
Views
4K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
3K
Replies
3
Views
2K
Back
Top