Proving Axioms for Addition and Multiplication: A Comprehensive Guide

  • MHB
  • Thread starter solakis1
  • Start date
In summary, we have a system of axioms that define a boolean system. Using these axioms, we can prove that if A+B=0, then A=0 and B=0. This is done by considering three cases: A=0 and B≠0, A≠0 and B=0, and A≠0 and B≠0. In each case, we use the axioms to show that A=0 and B=0. This allows us to conclude that if A+B=0, then A=0 and B=0.
  • #1
solakis1
422
0
Given the following system of axioms
For all A,B,C:

1) A+B=B+A

2) A+(B+C) =(A+B)+C

3) A.B=B.A

4) A.(B.C) = (A.B).C

5) A.(B+C)= A.B+A.C

6) A+0=A

7) A.1=A

8) A+(-A)=1

9) A.(-A)=0

10) A+(BC) = (A+B).(A+C)

11) \(\displaystyle 1\neq 0\)

Then prove :

If A+B=0 then A=0 AND B=0
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Re: axiomatics 2

I don't have time to solve it all, but maybe (Just maybe...) this can help.

\(\displaystyle A+1=A+1*1=(A+1)(A+1)=AA+A+A+1\) we've used A7,A5 and A10
\(\displaystyle A+1=AA+A+(A+1) => AA+A=0\) A6

so now we have AA+A= 0, we'll call this C1

\(\displaystyle 0=A+B=A+B*1=(A+B)(A+1)=AA+BA+A+B=BA+B\) We've used Hyp, A7,A10, A5 and C1.

\(\displaystyle BA+B=0 => B=A\) from C1

Now you must show that if \(\displaystyle A+A=0 \) then \(\displaystyle A=0\)

Note: I'm a bit tirred, I may have made a mistake.. (I hope not, but you know how it is..)

Hope this can help you a bit

edit: Those axioms aren't the one you use for real, I take for granted, this exercise is for fun only.
 
Last edited:
  • #3
Re: axiomatics 2

Barioth said:
I don't have time to solve it all, but maybe (Just maybe...) this can help.

\(\displaystyle A+1=A+1*1=(A+1)(A+1)=AA+A+A+1\) we've used A7,A5 and A10
\(\displaystyle A+1=AA+A+(A+1) => AA+A=0\) A6

so now we have AA+A= 0, we'll call this C1

\(\displaystyle 0=A+B=A+B*1=(A+B)(A+1)=AA+BA+A+B=BA+B\) We've used Hyp, A7,A10, A5 and C1.

\(\displaystyle BA+B=0 => B=A\) from C1

Now you must show that if \(\displaystyle A+A=0 \) then \(\displaystyle A=0\)

Note: I'm a bit tirred, I may have made a mistake.. (I hope not, but you know how it is..)

Hope this can help you a bit

edit: Those axioms aren't the one you use for real, I take for granted, this exercise is for fun only.
You have proved that :

A+1=0,but A+1 = 1 so you proved 1=0
But by axiom 11 we have :\(\displaystyle 1\neq 0\)

AA+BA+A+B=AA+BA

A.A=A,

A+A=ANothing is for fun in mathematics.

The above system is a boolean system

Thanks for the help anyway.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
Re: axiomatics 2

solakis said:
Nothing is for fun in mathematics.
Then I feel sorry for you...

solakis said:
The above system is a boolean system
This help a lot, next time, say so...

we have that A is 0 or 1 since A is a boolean.

we have 0+0 =0 from A6

we have 1+0=0+1 = 1 from A6 and A1

we only need to evalute 1+1 now

but we can get
A+1= (A+1)*1 from A7
(A+1)*1= (A+1)*(A+(-A)) from A9
(A+1)*(A+(-A))= A+(-A*1)=A+(-A) from A10 and A7
A+(-A)=1 from A8
so we have A+1 = 1 so 1+1=1.

This should solve your problem.
 
  • #5
Re: axiomatics 2

Barioth said:
Then I feel sorry for you...
we have that A is 0 or 1 since A is a boolean.

.

This is not always true:

For example if A,B,C are subsets of a set V ,with the well known operations of union intersection and complimentation,and with constants V and the empty set ,then we have a boolean system.

And definetelly we cannot say that each set is empty or V.

Hence your proof is not general.

It may have an application on the boolean system of propositional calculus
 
  • #6
solakis said:
Given the following system of axioms

For all A,B,C:

1) A+B=B+A
2) A+(B+C) =(A+B)+C
3) A.B=B.A
4) A.(B.C) = (A.B).C
5) A.(B+C)= A.B+A.C
6) A+0=A
7) A.1=A
8) A+(-A)=1
9) A.(-A)=0
10) A+(BC) = (A+B).(A+C)
11) \(\displaystyle 1\neq 0\)

Then prove :
If A+B=0 then A=0 AND B=0

Lemma L1: A.A = A
Proof: A = A.1 = A.(A+(-A)) = AA+A(-A) = AA+0 = AA. [using A7, A8, A5, A9, A6]

Lemma L2: A.0 = 0
Proof: A.0 = A.(A.(-A)) = (A.A).(-A) = A.(-A) = 0. [using A9, A4, L1, A9]

Suppose A≠0, B=0, and A+B=0.
Then A+B = A+0 = A ≠ 0. [using A6]

Suppose A=0, B≠0, and A+B=0.
Then A+B = 0+B = B+0 = B ≠ 0. [using A1, A6]

Suppose A≠0, B≠0, and A+B=0 (H1).
Then A = A+0 = A+B.0 = (A+B).(A+0) = 0.(A+0) = (A+0).0 = 0. [using A6, L2, A10, H1, A3, L2]

Therefore if A+B=0, then A=0 AND B=0.
 
  • #7
I like Serena said:
Lemma L1: A.A = A
Proof: A = A.1 = A.(A+(-A)) = AA+A(-A) = AA+0 = AA. [using A7, A8, A5, A9, A6]

Lemma L2: A.0 = 0
Proof: A.0 = A.(A.(-A)) = (A.A).(-A) = A.(-A) = 0. [using A9, A4, L1, A9]

Suppose A≠0, B=0, and A+B=0.
Then A+B = A+0 = A ≠ 0. [using A6]

Suppose A=0, B≠0, and A+B=0.
Then A+B = 0+B = B+0 = B ≠ 0. [using A1, A6]

Suppose A≠0, B≠0, and A+B=0 (H1).
Then A = A+0 = A+B.0 = (A+B).(A+0) = 0.(A+0) = (A+0).0 = 0. [using A6, L2, A10, H1, A3, L2]

Therefore if A+B=0, then A=0 AND B=0.

I am not so sure .

1) What law of logic make you to consider those three cases

2) Again what law of logic justifies the conclusion corresponding to those three hypothesis

3) What allows you to conclude : \(\displaystyle A+B\neq 0\) if A+B=A and \(\displaystyle A\neq 0\)
 
  • #8
mhm, this problem is pretty interesting, but shoudn't make so much touble...
 
  • #9
solakis said:
I am not so sure .

1) What law of logic make you to consider those three cases

The "law of the excluded middle":

In any case we are given that A+B = 0.

Either B = 0, or not. If B = 0, then either A = 0, or not.

If B = 0 and A = 0, there is nothing to prove, we already have the desired conclusion. Otherwise, we have B = 0, and A ≠ 0, which is case 1.

On the other hand if B ≠ 0, then either A = 0, or not. The first case is case 2, the latter is case 3.

2) Again what law of logic justifies the conclusion corresponding to those three hypothesis

The axioms you listed in your first post, which are taken to hold for ALL elements of the system under consideration.

3) What allows you to conclude : \(\displaystyle A+B\neq 0\) if A+B=A and \(\displaystyle A\neq 0\)

Let's go step-by-step through case (1):

Assumptions: A ≠ 0, B = 0, A + B = 0.

Since B = 0 (that is B is identical to 0), the expression A + B is the same as the expression A + 0. This is called "substituting the value 0 in for B", which we can do because they are EQUAL.

Now A + 0 = A, by axiom 6.

So A + B = A + 0 = A, thus A + B = A, by transitivity of equality.

Since A ≠ 0, and A + B = A, we must have A + B ≠ 0, for if we had

A + B = 0, then:

0 = A + B (by symmetry of equality)

A + B = A, and thus:

0 = A (by transitivity of equality), and thus A = 0 (by symmetry of equality).

But this violates our original assumption that A ≠ 0:

something cannot be both equal and not equal to something else.

This is another consequence of the law of the excluded middle, which can be stated as either:

P or not-P = TRUE (tautological form)

or:

P and not-P = FALSE (contradiction form).

******

In mathematics, a bivalent system of truth based on a boolean system of logic (satisfying the above axioms you gave with:

1 <--> "true"
0 <--> "false"
+ <--> "or"
. <--> "and"
- <--> "not")

is usually taken as a GIVEN, unless you are a constructivist (or intuitionist), in which case a DIRECT proof must be exibited.

Let's see if a direct proof is possible for this theorem (using the axioms given).

By A1, it is sufficient to prove that:

A + B = 0 implies A = 0, since we can just switch the roles of A and B to prove that:

A + B = 0 implies B + A = 0 implies B = 0, by the proof we are about to demonstrate:

A + B = 0 (given)

(A + B).1 = 0 (from A7)

(A + B).(A + (-A)) = 0 (from A8)

A + (B.(-A)) = 0 (from A10)

A + ((B.(-A)) + 0) = 0 (from A6, applied to B.(-A))

A + ((B.(-A)) + (A.(-A))) = 0 (from A9)

A + (((-A).B) + ((-A).A)) = 0 (using A3 twice, on B.(-A) and A.(-A))

A + ((-A).(B + A)) = 0 (using A5, applied to ((-A).B) + ((-A).A))

A + ((-A).(A + B)) = 0 (using A1, applied to B + A)

A + ((-A).0) = 0 (using our given A + B = 0)

A + 0 = 0 (using L2 proved by ILikeSerena, applied to (-A).0)

A = 0 (using A6).
 
  • #10
Deveno said:
The "law of the excluded middle":

In any case we are given that A+B = 0.

Either B = 0, or not. If B = 0, then either A = 0, or not.

If B = 0 and A = 0, there is nothing to prove, we already have the desired conclusion. Otherwise, we have B = 0, and A ≠ 0, which is case 1.

On the other hand if B ≠ 0, then either A = 0, or not. The first case is case 2, the latter is case 3.
The axioms you listed in your first post, which are taken to hold for ALL elements of the system under consideration.
Let's go step-by-step through case (1):

Assumptions: A ≠ 0, B = 0, A + B = 0.

Since B = 0 (that is B is identical to 0), the expression A + B is the same as the expression A + 0. This is called "substituting the value 0 in for B", which we can do because they are EQUAL.

Now A + 0 = A, by axiom 6.

So A + B = A + 0 = A, thus A + B = A, by transitivity of equality.

Since A ≠ 0, and A + B = A, we must have A + B ≠ 0, for if we had

A + B = 0, then:

0 = A + B (by symmetry of equality)

A + B = A, and thus:

0 = A (by transitivity of equality), and thus A = 0 (by symmetry of equality).

But this violates our original assumption that A ≠ 0:

something cannot be both equal and not equal to something else.

This is another consequence of the law of the excluded middle, which can be stated as either:

P or not-P = TRUE (tautological form)

or:

P and not-P = FALSE (contradiction form).

******

In mathematics, a bivalent system of truth based on a boolean system of logic (satisfying the above axioms you gave with:

1 <--> "true"
0 <--> "false"
+ <--> "or"
. <--> "and"
- <--> "not")

is usually taken as a GIVEN, unless you are a constructivist (or intuitionist), in which case a DIRECT proof must be exibited.

Let's see if a direct proof is possible for this theorem (using the axioms given).

By A1, it is sufficient to prove that:

A + B = 0 implies A = 0, since we can just switch the roles of A and B to prove that:

A + B = 0 implies B + A = 0 implies B = 0, by the proof we are about to demonstrate:

A + B = 0 (given)

(A + B).1 = 0 (from A7)

(A + B).(A + (-A)) = 0 (from A8)

A + (B.(-A)) = 0 (from A10)

A + ((B.(-A)) + 0) = 0 (from A6, applied to B.(-A))

A + ((B.(-A)) + (A.(-A))) = 0 (from A9)

A + (((-A).B) + ((-A).A)) = 0 (using A3 twice, on B.(-A) and A.(-A))

A + ((-A).(B + A)) = 0 (using A5, applied to ((-A).B) + ((-A).A))

A + ((-A).(A + B)) = 0 (using A1, applied to B + A)

A + ((-A).0) = 0 (using our given A + B = 0)

A + 0 = 0 (using L2 proved by ILikeSerena, applied to (-A).0)

A = 0 (using A6).

O.K let's take your proof step by step:

How do you go from : A+B=0 to (A+B).1=0??

Because A7 tells you that : A.1 =A

And certainly does not tell you how to go from A+B=0 to (A+B).1 =0
 
  • #11
A + B = 0 (given)

(A + B).1 = A + B (A7, which applies to ANY element of our system, including A+B)

(A + B).1 = 0 (transitivity of equality).

The axiom:

A.1 = A for all A

doesn't mean A.1 = A "just for A", but rather:

A.1 = A
B.1 = B
C.1 = C
X.1 = X, where X is any legal expression formed from elements {A,B,C,...etc.} and the symbols +,. and - (which are binary (the first two) and unary (the last one) operations), perhaps appropriately grouped with parentheses.

Your axiom system is a bit abbreviated, it should mention an underlying set of elements, the fact that + and . are binary operations, that - is a unary operation, that there are two distinguished elements of our underlying set 0 and 1 with special properties (defined by axioms 6,7,8,9 and 11). However these things are "standard" when studying axiomatic systems.

So formally, we have a system:

U = {S,+,.,-,1,0}

where + is a function

SxS --> S

and . is a function

SxS -->S

and - is a function

S-->S

and 1,0 are elements of S

such that axioms 1 through 11 hold for all elements of S.

The fact that - is a function S-->S is often stated instead like so:

For every A in S, there is a unique B in S such that:

A + B = 1 and A.B = 0

in which case B is denoted -A.

The uniqueness requirement is often omitted, however, because if:

A + B = A + C = 1 and
A.B = A.C = 0

Then (-A).(A + B) = (-A).(A + C) so:

(-A.A) + (-A.B) = (-A.A) + (-A.C)

0 + (-A.B) = 0 + (-A.C)

-A.B = -A.C

and from

A.B = A.C = 0, we have:

A.B + (-A.B) = A.C + (-A.C)

(A + (-A)).B = (A + (-A)).C

1.B = 1.C

B.1 = C.1

B = C

I leave it as an exercise for you to consider which axioms justify each step above.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Deveno said:
A + B = 0 (given)

(A + B).1 = A + B (A7, which applies to ANY element of our system, including A+B)

(A + B).1 = 0 (transitivity of equality).

But the rule of transitivity says:

IF X=Y and Y=Z Then X=Z

So if we put : X= (A+B).1 , Y= A+B, Z=0

WE have :

IF (A+B).1 =A+B and A+B= 0 ,THEN (A+B).1=0

And now how do we get: (A+B).1 =0??
 
  • #13
(A+B).1 = A+B is guaranteed by axiom 7.

A+B = 0 is given as a premise of the problem.

So the "if" part is satisfied, and thus we can conclude the "then" part.
 
  • #14
Deveno said:
(A+B).1 = A+B is guaranteed by axiom 7.

A+B = 0 is given as a premise of the problem.

So the "if" part is satisfied, and thus we can conclude the "then" part.

Iam not so sure about your reasoning.

for example if we say :

IF 2+2=4 THEN 3+2=6

The "if" part is satisfied because 2+2=4
Can we conclude 3+2=6 ??
 
  • #15
The "if...then" statement known as the transitivity of equality is a true statement. It's one of several statements in mathematics that are taken as "axiomatically true" or "true by definition".

By contrast, your statement:

If 2 +2 = 4 then 3 + 2 = 6

is logically false, because while 2+2 = 4 is indeed true, 3 + 2 = 6 is not:

T-->T = T
T-->F = F

(statements of the form F-->anything are typically not considered in math, because anything can be proven from a false premise, so no useful knowledge is revealed).

The transitivity of equality:

If A = B and B = C, then A = C

is taken to be true A PRIORI. In ordinary language, this translates to the idea:

If thing 1 is exactly the same thing as thing 2, and thing 2 is exactly the same thing as thing 3, then all three things are the same thing.

In practice, we use such transitivity to establish such things as:

10 = 5 + 5
5 + 5 = 4 + 6

therefore, 10 = 4 + 6.

If you are uncomfortable with the reflexive, symmetric and transitive nature of equality, I suggest you give up on the pursuit of mathematics entirely, as you will no doubt encounter many grave difficulties.

Just to be clear, I am not suggesting ANY if...then clause can be verified solely by verifying the "if" part, but rather, any INSTANCE of transitivity can be justified by showing the antecedent clause of the rule of transitivity is satisfied, thus allowing us to safely (by invoking the rule of transitivity) deduce the consequent.

A bit more formally (but perhaps more mystifying):

1) $\forall X,Y,Z: [(X = Y)\wedge(Y = Z)] \implies (X = Z)$ (given, rule of transitivity)
2) $X = Y$ (given)
3) $Y = Z$ (given)
4) $(X = Y)\wedge(Y = Z)$ (conjunction introduction, 2,3)
5) $X = Z$ (modus ponens, 1,4)

By contrast, we cannot derive B from A, given only that A is true (your argument): both A AND A-->B must BOTH be true.
 
  • #16
Deveno said:
The "if...then" statement known as the transitivity of equality is a true statement. It's one of several statements in mathematics that are taken as "axiomatically true" or "true by definition".

By contrast, your statement:

If 2 +2 = 4 then 3 + 2 = 6

is logically false, because while 2+2 = 4 is indeed true, 3 + 2 = 6 is not:

T-->T = T
T-->F = F

(statements of the form F-->anything are typically not considered in math, because anything can be proven from a false premise, so no useful knowledge is revealed).

The transitivity of equality:

If A = B and B = C, then A = C

is taken to be true A PRIORI. In ordinary language, this translates to the idea:

If thing 1 is exactly the same thing as thing 2, and thing 2 is exactly the same thing as thing 3, then all three things are the same thing.

In practice, we use such transitivity to establish such things as:

10 = 5 + 5
5 + 5 = 4 + 6

therefore, 10 = 4 + 6.

If you are uncomfortable with the reflexive, symmetric and transitive nature of equality, I suggest you give up on the pursuit of mathematics entirely, as you will no doubt encounter many grave difficulties.

Just to be clear, I am not suggesting ANY if...then clause can be verified solely by verifying the "if" part, but rather, any INSTANCE of transitivity can be justified by showing the antecedent clause of the rule of transitivity is satisfied, thus allowing us to safely (by invoking the rule of transitivity) deduce the consequent.

A bit more formally (but perhaps more mystifying):

1) $\forall X,Y,Z: [(X = Y)\wedge(Y = Z)] \implies (X = Z)$ (given, rule of transitivity)
2) $X = Y$ (given)
3) $Y = Z$ (given)
4) $(X = Y)\wedge(Y = Z)$ (conjunction introduction, 2,3)
5) $X = Z$ (modus ponens, 1,4)

By contrast, we cannot derive B from A, given only that A is true (your argument): both A AND A-->B must BOTH be true.

So:
A)The argument:
If (A+B).1=A+B and A+B=0,then (A+B).1=0,and since (A+B).1=A+B and A+B=0
We have :
(A+B).1=0
Is correct
Whilst
The argument:
If 2+2=4,then 2+3=5 and since 2+2=4
We have:
2+3=5
Is not correct
B) According to the last part of your post we have:
1)A+B=0…………………………………………………………given
2)(A+B).1 = A+B…………………………………………………axiom A.1=A
3)(A+B).1 = A+B and A+B=0 => (A+B).1=0…………………………transitivity property
4) )(A+B).1 = A+B and A+B=0…………………………………………..1,2 Addition property
5) (A+B).1=0………………………………………………………………………3,4 M.ponens
Can you do the rest of the proof in that style ??
 
  • #17
I probably could, but if you really want a formal style proof Evgeny.Makarov is a much better person for that sort of thing. I lean more towards algebraic arguments, not logical propositions.
 
  • #18
Deveno said:
I probably could, but if you really want a formal style proof Evgeny.Makarov is a much better person for that sort of thing. I lean more towards algebraic arguments, not logical propositions.

What does a algebraic argument consists of

What is a logical proposition

Pardon me but i am so sure yet while my argument :

If 2+2=4,then 2+3=6,but since 2+2=4 ,then 3+3=6is correct or not
 
  • #19
solakis said:
Iam not so sure about your reasoning.

for example if we say :

IF 2+2=4 THEN 3+2=6

The "if" part is satisfied because 2+2=4
Can we conclude 3+2=6 ??
Yes, we can. This argument is valid, but it is not sound because the premise "IF 2+2=4 THEN 3+2=6" is not true.
 
  • #20
Evgeny.Makarov said:
Yes, we can. This argument is valid, but it is not sound because the premise "IF 2+2=4 THEN 3+2=6" is not true.

Are the following arguments valid and sound:

if 2+3=6 then 2+2=4,therefor 2+2=4

If i go to London i will buy a car,therefor i will buy a car
 
  • #21
solakis said:
Are the following arguments valid and sound:

if 2+3=6 then 2+2=4,therefor 2+2=4
There are two options regarding validity. If we insist on deriving 2+2=4 from "If 2+3=6 then 2+2=4", i.e., if the argument is complete and there is no way to derive 2+2=4 using some other reasoning that is not shown, then the argument is not valid. It has the form "$A\to B$, $B$", and this transition does not conform to any of the inference rules. Modus Ponens could be used to derive $B$ from $A\to B$, but then the argument must also contain a proof of $A$.

The second option is that the argument is abbreviated and 2+2=4 is derived not from "If 2+3=6 then 2+2=4", but using other means that are not shown; for example, 2+2=4 is an axiom. Then the argument is valid. The premise "If 2+3=6 then 2+2=4" is simply not used.

solakis said:
If i go to London i will buy a car,therefor i will buy a car
This argument is either incomplete or invalid. Again, there are two options: either you derive "I will buy a car" essentially using the premise "If I go to London, I will buy a car", or you derive it without using that premise, using some independent means. In the first case, you also need to prove "I will go to London" in order to use Modus Ponens. In the second case, the argument is incomplete, and without extra information there is less reason to think that you will buy a car than to believe that 2 + 2 = 4.
 
  • #22
I'd like to point out that statements like:

"IF 2+3 = 6, THEN 2+2 = 4"

are usually not considered within mathematical study.

This is actually a TRUE statement, because it can be proved by other means that "2+2 = 4" is a true statement, but the fact that 2+2 = 4 is NOT a consequence of the statement 2+3 = 6.

The situation we find ourselves in is usually this:

We want to know what happens if "A" happens to be true. For example:

Given that:

k + 0 = k, for all integers k

are we now in a position to explicitly evaluate 0+0?

We reason:

1. k + 0 = k, for all integers k
2. 0 is an integer (discovered by some other means, perhaps, taken as given here)
3. 0 + 0 = 0 (1, using k = 0...this is an example of substitution or instantiation-replacing a logical variable with a logical constant)

Often (1) is even given in the form:

1. There exists an integer 0, such that k + 0 = k, for all integers k

which eliminates the need for (2).

We conclude that:

k + 0 = k implies 0 + 0 = 0.

Somewhat confusingly, logical variables are often replaced by other logical variables, as we do here:

(1a) for all X in S, X + 0 = X (given)
(2a) A + B in S (given)
(3a) (A + B) + 0 = A + B (replacing the variable X with the variable A + B in (1)).

We might even replace X, with another variable dependent on X, such as X + X:

(2b) X + X in S
(3b) (X + X) + 0 = X + X

We would still conclude that:

(1a) implies (3a)

or:

(1a) implies (3b).

Usually, (3a) or (3b) is the statement we actually want to USE, it is very likely we have yet ANOTHER implication statement that will use IT as its antecedent.

Now, if (1a) turned out not to be true, all of our effort is for naught. The statements we wish to derive from it, might still be true, but we would need another way to establish that.

Axiomatic statements are usually accepted as "given" or true a priori. Occasionally this process is "reversed" in mathematics, the most famous example being the revision of the axiom of comprehension in set theory, which had to be modified because it lead to paradoxes (Russel sets).

When one is studying vector spaces, for example, there are many theorems that begin:

If $V$ is a finite-dimensional vector space, then...

Now there are many infinite-dimensional vector spaces, and such theorems may, or may not be true for these. In any case, however, the PROOFS of those theorems are not valid for the infinite-dimensional case...even if the conclusion of the original theorem is still true in the infinite-dimensional case.

Proof, in mathematics is used in two different senses, one formal and one informal.

In a formal proof, one defines an alphabet, some rules, and a logical system (usually, but not always, the classical first-order predicate logic, or something "equivalent" to it which can prove the same statements) and creates an algorithm by which the derivation of B from A could be done mechanically.

In an informal proof, the idea is to communicate enough of the skeleton of a formal proof, so that it is convincing. Implication is often buried in such phrases as:

"And we see that..."

"Now, as a consequence..."

"It suffices that..."

or the pithy:

"So..."

Instructors in any given mathematical course often differ as to the level of formalism required, and this can even vary with the SAME instructor in two different courses (rather more formalism is to be expected in a course on mathematical logic than say, in combinatorics). As such, when a question is posed on these forums, it is not always a straight-forward matter to determine what degree of sophistication and/or formality is required in our responses.
 
  • #23
Evgeny.Makarov said:
There are two options regarding validity. If we insist on deriving 2+2=4 from "If 2+3=6 then 2+2=4", i.e., if the argument is complete and there is no way to derive 2+2=4 using some other reasoning that is not shown, then the argument is not valid. It has the form "$A\to B$, $B$", and this transition does not conform to any of the inference rules. Modus Ponens could be used to derive $B$ from $A\to B$, but then the argument must also contain a proof of $A$.

The second option is that the argument is abbreviated and 2+2=4 is derived not from "If 2+3=6 then 2+2=4", but using other means that are not shown; for example, 2+2=4 is an axiom. Then the argument is valid. The premise "If 2+3=6 then 2+2=4" is simply not used.

This argument is either incomplete or invalid. Again, there are two options: either you derive "I will buy a car" essentially using the premise "If I go to London, I will buy a car", or you derive it without using that premise, using some independent means. In the first case, you also need to prove "I will go to London" in order to use Modus Ponens. In the second case, the argument is incomplete, and without extra information there is less reason to think that you will buy a car than to believe that 2 + 2 = 4.
I am afraid to say you have not given me a solid pfoof whether the two statements are valid or not.

A proof based on adefinition or a theorem or an axiom of the symbolic logic stating clearly when an argument is valid or not
 
  • #24
Deveno said:
I'd like to point out that statements like:

"IF 2+3 = 6, THEN 2+2 = 4"

are usually not considered within mathematical study.

This is actually a TRUE statement, because it can be proved by other means that "2+2 = 4" is a true statement, but the fact that 2+2 = 4 is NOT a consequence of the statement 2+3 = 6.

The situation we find ourselves in is usually this:

We want to know what happens if "A" happens to be true. For example:

Given that:

k + 0 = k, for all integers k

are we now in a position to explicitly evaluate 0+0?

We reason:

1. k + 0 = k, for all integers k
2. 0 is an integer (discovered by some other means, perhaps, taken as given here)
3. 0 + 0 = 0 (1, using k = 0...this is an example of substitution or instantiation-replacing a logical variable with a logical constant)

Often (1) is even given in the form:

1. There exists an integer 0, such that k + 0 = k, for all integers k

which eliminates the need for (2).

We conclude that:

k + 0 = k implies 0 + 0 = 0.

Somewhat confusingly, logical variables are often replaced by other logical variables, as we do here:

(1a) for all X in S, X + 0 = X (given)
(2a) A + B in S (given)
(3a) (A + B) + 0 = A + B (replacing the variable X with the variable A + B in (1)).

We might even replace X, with another variable dependent on X, such as X + X:

(2b) X + X in S
(3b) (X + X) + 0 = X + X

We would still conclude that:

(1a) implies (3a)

or:

(1a) implies (3b).

Usually, (3a) or (3b) is the statement we actually want to USE, it is very likely we have yet ANOTHER implication statement that will use IT as its antecedent.

Now, if (1a) turned out not to be true, all of our effort is for naught. The statements we wish to derive from it, might still be true, but we would need another way to establish that.

Axiomatic statements are usually accepted as "given" or true a priori. Occasionally this process is "reversed" in mathematics, the most famous example being the revision of the axiom of comprehension in set theory, which had to be modified because it lead to paradoxes (Russel sets).

When one is studying vector spaces, for example, there are many theorems that begin:

If $V$ is a finite-dimensional vector space, then...

Now there are many infinite-dimensional vector spaces, and such theorems may, or may not be true for these. In any case, however, the PROOFS of those theorems are not valid for the infinite-dimensional case...even if the conclusion of the original theorem is still true in the infinite-dimensional case.

Proof, in mathematics is used in two different senses, one formal and one informal.

In a formal proof, one defines an alphabet, some rules, and a logical system (usually, but not always, the classical first-order predicate logic, or something "equivalent" to it which can prove the same statements) and creates an algorithm by which the derivation of B from A could be done mechanically.

In an informal proof, the idea is to communicate enough of the skeleton of a formal proof, so that it is convincing. Implication is often buried in such phrases as:

"And we see that..."

"Now, as a consequence..."

"It suffices that..."

or the pithy:

"So..."

Instructors in any given mathematical course often differ as to the level of formalism required, and this can even vary with the SAME instructor in two different courses (rather more formalism is to be expected in a course on mathematical logic than say, in combinatorics). As such, when a question is posed on these forums, it is not always a straight-forward matter to determine what degree of sophistication and/or formality is required in our responses.
Does the above answer my questions:

1) What an algebraic argument consists of

2) What is a logical proposition ??
 
  • #25
solakis said:
Does the above answer my questions:

1) What an algebraic argument consists of

2) What is a logical proposition ??

No, I'm afraid it doesn't. I feel that #2 is easier to answer in some contexts, but there's a few things you have to define before-hand (atoms, connectives, and allowed combinations of these).

#1 is somewhat problematic: most algebraic arguments fall into the "informal" category, it is assumed before-hand that the reader is somewhat accustomed to how these things go.

An example:

Proof that the additive identity (zero) of the integers is unique:

Assume that $e \neq 0$ is another additive identity.

Then $0 = 0 + e = e$, contradiction.

Obviously, as a formal proof, this has several flaws, but it is nonetheless typical of proofs you would find in an algebra textbook; and the reasoning behind it should be clear.
 

Related to Proving Axioms for Addition and Multiplication: A Comprehensive Guide

1. What is the purpose of proving axioms for addition and multiplication?

The purpose of proving axioms for addition and multiplication is to establish a set of basic rules or principles that are universally accepted and can be used to reason about these operations. These axioms serve as the foundation for further mathematical concepts and proofs.

2. How are axioms for addition and multiplication different from other mathematical axioms?

Axioms for addition and multiplication are unique in that they specifically govern the operations of addition and multiplication, while other mathematical axioms may apply to a broader range of mathematical concepts. Additionally, axioms for addition and multiplication are often considered to be more intuitive and self-evident, making them easier to understand and apply.

3. What are some common axioms for addition and multiplication?

Some common axioms for addition include the commutative property (a + b = b + a), the associative property ((a + b) + c = a + (b + c)), and the identity property (a + 0 = a). For multiplication, common axioms include the commutative property (ab = ba), the associative property ((ab)c = a(bc)), and the distributive property (a(b+c) = ab + ac).

4. How do you prove axioms for addition and multiplication?

Axioms for addition and multiplication are typically proven using mathematical reasoning and logic. This may involve using previously established axioms and theorems, as well as using mathematical operations and properties to show that the axiom holds true in all cases.

5. Can axioms for addition and multiplication be disproven?

No, axioms for addition and multiplication cannot be disproven because they are considered to be self-evident and universally accepted. However, they can be refined or expanded upon as new mathematical concepts and principles are discovered.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
978
Replies
1
Views
662
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
6
Views
817
  • General Math
Replies
16
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
26
Views
4K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
2
Views
468
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
5
Views
2K
Back
Top